-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
UseTactics.v
1073 lines (856 loc) · 36.7 KB
/
UseTactics.v
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
(** * UseTactics: Tactic Library for Coq: A Gentle Introduction *)
(* Chapter written and maintained by Arthur Chargueraud *)
(** Coq comes with a set of builtin tactics, such as [reflexivity],
[intros], [inversion] and so on. While it is possible to conduct
proofs using only those tactics, you can significantly increase
your productivity by working with a set of more powerful tactics.
This chapter describes a number of such useful tactics, which, for
various reasons, are not yet available by default in Coq. These
tactics are defined in the [LibTactics.v] file. *)
Require Import Coq.Arith.Arith.
Require Import Maps.
Require Import Imp.
Require Import Types.
Require Import Smallstep.
Require Import LibTactics.
(** Remark: SSReflect is another package providing powerful tactics.
The library "LibTactics" differs from "SSReflect" in two respects:
- "SSReflect" was primarily developed for proving mathematical
theorems, whereas "LibTactics" was primarily developed for proving
theorems on programming languages. In particular, "LibTactics"
provides a number of useful tactics that have no counterpart in the
"SSReflect" package.
- "SSReflect" entirely rethinks the presentation of tactics,
whereas "LibTactics" mostly stick to the traditional
presentation of Coq tactics, simply providing a number of
additional tactics. For this reason, "LibTactics" is
probably easier to get started with than "SSReflect". *)
(** This chapter is a tutorial focusing on the most useful features
from the "LibTactics" library. It does not aim at presenting all
the features of "LibTactics". The detailed specification of tactics
can be found in the source file [LibTactics.v]. Further documentation
as well as demos can be found at http://www.chargueraud.org/softs/tlc/. *)
(** In this tutorial, tactics are presented using examples taken from
the core chapters of the "Software Foundations" course. To illustrate
the various ways in which a given tactic can be used, we use a
tactic that duplicates a given goal. More precisely, [dup] produces
two copies of the current goal, and [dup n] produces [n] copies of it. *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Tactics for Introduction and Case Analysis *)
(** This section presents the following tactics:
- [introv], for naming hypotheses more efficiently,
- [inverts], for improving the [inversion] tactic,
- [cases], for performing a case analysis without losing information,
- [cases_if], for automating case analysis on the argument of [if]. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [introv] *)
Module IntrovExamples.
Require Import Stlc.
Import Imp STLC.
(** The tactic [introv] allows to automatically introduce the
variables of a theorem and explicitly name the hypotheses
involved. In the example shown next, the variables [c],
[st], [st1] and [st2] involved in the statement of determinism
need not be named explicitly, because their name where already
given in the statement of the lemma. On the contrary, it is
useful to provide names for the two hypotheses, which we
name [E1] and [E2], respectively. *)
Theorem ceval_deterministic: forall c st st1 st2,
c / st \\ st1 ->
c / st \\ st2 ->
st1 = st2.
Proof.
introv E1 E2. (* was [intros c st st1 st2 E1 E2] *)
Abort.
(** When there is no hypothesis to be named, one can call
[introv] without any argument. *)
Theorem dist_exists_or : forall (X:Type) (P Q : X -> Prop),
(exists x, P x \/ Q x) <-> (exists x, P x) \/ (exists x, Q x).
Proof.
introv. (* was [intros X P Q] *)
Abort.
(** The tactic [introv] also applies to statements in which
[forall] and [->] are interleaved. *)
Theorem ceval_deterministic': forall c st st1,
(c / st \\ st1) -> forall st2, (c / st \\ st2) -> st1 = st2.
Proof.
introv E1 E2. (* was [intros c st st1 E1 st2 E2] *)
Abort.
(** Like the arguments of [intros], the arguments of [introv]
can be structured patterns. *)
Theorem exists_impl: forall X (P : X -> Prop) (Q : Prop) (R : Prop),
(forall x, P x -> Q) ->
((exists x, P x) -> Q).
Proof.
introv [x H2]. eauto.
(* same as [intros X P Q R H1 [x H2].], which is itself short
for [intros X P Q R H1 H2. destruct H2 as [x H2].] *)
Qed.
(** Remark: the tactic [introv] works even when definitions
need to be unfolded in order to reveal hypotheses. *)
End IntrovExamples.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [inverts] *)
Module InvertsExamples.
Require Import Stlc Equiv Imp.
Import STLC.
(** The [inversion] tactic of Coq is not very satisfying for
three reasons. First, it produces a bunch of equalities
which one typically wants to substitute away, using [subst].
Second, it introduces meaningless names for hypotheses.
Third, a call to [inversion H] does not remove [H] from the
context, even though in most cases an hypothesis is no longer
needed after being inverted. The tactic [inverts] address all
of these three issues. It is intented to be used in place of
the tactic [inversion]. *)
(** The following example illustrates how the tactic [inverts H]
behaves mostly like [inversion H] except that it performs
some substitutions in order to eliminate the trivial equalities
that are being produced by [inversion]. *)
Theorem skip_left: forall c,
cequiv (SKIP;; c) c.
Proof.
introv. split; intros H.
dup. (* duplicate the goal for comparison *)
(* was... *)
- inversion H. subst. inversion H2. subst. assumption.
(* now... *)
- inverts H. inverts H2. assumption.
Abort.
(** A slightly more interesting example appears next. *)
Theorem ceval_deterministic: forall c st st1 st2,
c / st \\ st1 ->
c / st \\ st2 ->
st1 = st2.
Proof.
introv E1 E2. generalize dependent st2.
induction E1; intros st2 E2.
admit. admit. (* skip some basic cases *)
dup. (* duplicate the goal for comparison *)
(* was: *)
- inversion E2. subst. admit.
(* now: *)
- inverts E2. admit.
Abort.
(** The tactic [inverts H as.] is like [inverts H] except that the
variables and hypotheses being produced are placed in the goal
rather than in the context. This strategy allows naming those
new variables and hypotheses explicitly, using either [intros]
or [introv]. *)
Theorem ceval_deterministic': forall c st st1 st2,
c / st \\ st1 ->
c / st \\ st2 ->
st1 = st2.
Proof.
introv E1 E2. generalize dependent st2.
(induction E1); intros st2 E2;
inverts E2 as.
- (* E_Skip *) reflexivity.
- (* E_Ass *)
(* Observe that the variable [n] is not automatically
substituted because, contrary to [inversion E2; subst],
the tactic [inverts E2] does not substitute the equalities
that exist before running the inversion. *)
(* new: *) subst n.
reflexivity.
- (* E_Seq *)
(* Here, the newly created variables can be introduced
using intros, so they can be assigned meaningful names,
for example [st3] instead of [st'0]. *)
(* new: *) intros st3 Red1 Red2.
assert (st' = st3) as EQ1.
{ (* Proof of assertion *) apply IHE1_1; assumption. }
subst st3.
apply IHE1_2. assumption.
(* E_IfTrue *)
- (* b1 reduces to true *)
(* In an easy case like this one, there is no need to
provide meaningful names, so we can just use [intros] *)
(* new: *) intros.
apply IHE1. assumption.
- (* b1 reduces to false (contradiction) *)
(* new: *) intros.
rewrite H in H5. inversion H5.
(* The other cases are similiar *)
Abort.
(** In the particular case where a call to [inversion] produces
a single subgoal, one can use the syntax [inverts H as H1 H2 H3]
for calling [inverts] and naming the new hypotheses [H1], [H2]
and [H3]. In other words, the tactic [inverts H as H1 H2 H3] is
equivalent to [inverts H as; introv H1 H2 H3]. An example follows. *)
Theorem skip_left': forall c,
cequiv (SKIP;; c) c.
Proof.
introv. split; intros H.
inverts H as U V. (* new hypotheses are named [U] and [V] *)
inverts U. assumption.
Abort.
(** A more involved example appears next. In particular, this example
shows that the name of the hypothesis being inverted can be reused. *)
Example typing_nonexample_1 :
~ exists T,
has_type empty
(tabs x TBool
(tabs y TBool
(tapp (tvar x) (tvar y))))
T.
Proof.
dup 3.
(* The old proof: *)
- intros C. destruct C.
inversion H. subst. clear H.
inversion H5. subst. clear H5.
inversion H4. subst. clear H4.
inversion H2. subst. clear H2.
inversion H5. subst. clear H5.
inversion H1.
(* The new proof: *)
- intros C. destruct C.
inverts H as H1.
inverts H1 as H2.
inverts H2 as H3.
inverts H3 as H4.
inverts H4.
(* The new proof, alternative: *)
- intros C. destruct C.
inverts H as H.
inverts H as H.
inverts H as H.
inverts H as H.
inverts H.
Qed.
End InvertsExamples.
(** Note: in the rare cases where one needs to perform an inversion
on an hypothesis [H] without clearing [H] from the context,
one can use the tactic [inverts keep H], where the keyword [keep]
indicates that the hypothesis should be kept in the context. *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Tactics for N-ary Connectives *)
(** Because Coq encodes conjunctions and disjunctions using binary
constructors [/\] and [\/], working with a conjunction or a
disjunction of [N] facts can sometimes be quite cumbursome.
For this reason, "LibTactics" provides tactics offering direct
support for n-ary conjunctions and disjunctions. It also provides
direct support for n-ary existententials. *)
(** This section presents the following tactics:
- [splits] for decomposing n-ary conjunctions,
- [branch] for decomposing n-ary disjunctions,
- [exists] for proving n-ary existentials. *)
Module NaryExamples.
Require Import References SfLib.
Import STLCRef.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [splits] *)
(** The tactic [splits] applies to a goal made of a conjunction
of [n] propositions and it produces [n] subgoals. For example,
it decomposes the goal [G1 /\ G2 /\ G3] into the three subgoals
[G1], [G2] and [G3]. *)
Lemma demo_splits : forall n m,
n > 0 /\ n < m /\ m < n+10 /\ m <> 3.
Proof.
intros. splits.
Abort.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [branch] *)
(** The tactic [branch k] can be used to prove a n-ary disjunction.
For example, if the goal takes the form [G1 \/ G2 \/ G3],
the tactic [branch 2] leaves only [G2] as subgoal. The following
example illustrates the behavior of the [branch] tactic. *)
Lemma demo_branch : forall n m,
n < m \/ n = m \/ m < n.
Proof.
intros.
destruct (lt_eq_lt_dec n m) as [[H1|H2]|H3].
- branch 1. apply H1.
- branch 2. apply H2.
- branch 3. apply H3.
Qed.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [exists] *)
(** The library "LibTactics" introduces a notation for n-ary
existentials. For example, one can write [exists x y z, H]
instead of [exists x, exists y, exists z, H]. Similarly,
the library provides a n-ary tactic [exists a b c], which is a
shorthand for [exists a; exists b; exists c]. The following
example illustrates both the notation and the tactic for
dealing with n-ary existentials. *)
Theorem progress : forall ST t T st,
has_type empty ST t T ->
store_well_typed ST st ->
value t \/ exists t' st', t / st ==> t' / st'.
(* was: [value t \/ exists t', exists st', t / st ==> t' / st'] *)
Proof with eauto.
intros ST t T st Ht HST. remember (@empty ty) as Gamma.
(induction Ht); subst; try solve by inversion...
- (* T_App *)
right. destruct IHHt1 as [Ht1p | Ht1p]...
+ (* t1 is a value *)
inversion Ht1p; subst; try solve by inversion.
destruct IHHt2 as [Ht2p | Ht2p]...
(* t2 steps *)
inversion Ht2p as [t2' [st' Hstep]].
exists (tapp (tabs x T t) t2') st'...
(* was: [exists (tapp (tabs x T t) t2'). exists st'...] *)
Abort.
(** Remark: a similar facility for n-ary existentials is provided
by the module [Coq.Program.Syntax] from the standard library.
([Coq.Program.Syntax] supports existentials up to arity 4;
[LibTactics] supports them up to arity 10. *)
End NaryExamples.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Tactics for Working with Equality *)
(** One of the major weakness of Coq compared with other interactive
proof assistants is its relatively poor support for reasoning
with equalities. The tactics described next aims at simplifying
pieces of proof scripts manipulating equalities. *)
(** This section presents the following tactics:
- [asserts_rewrite] for introducing an equality to rewrite with,
- [cuts_rewrite], which is similar except that its subgoals are swapped,
- [substs] for improving the [subst] tactic,
- [fequals] for improving the [f_equal] tactic,
- [applys_eq] for proving [P x y] using an hypothesis [P x z],
automatically producing an equality [y = z] as subgoal. *)
Module EqualityExamples.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactics [asserts_rewrite] and [cuts_rewrite] *)
(** The tactic [asserts_rewrite (E1 = E2)] replaces [E1] with [E2] in
the goal, and produces the goal [E1 = E2]. *)
Theorem mult_0_plus : forall n m : nat,
(0 + n) * m = n * m.
Proof.
dup.
(* The old proof: *)
intros n m.
assert (H: 0 + n = n). reflexivity. rewrite -> H.
reflexivity.
(* The new proof: *)
intros n m.
asserts_rewrite (0 + n = n).
reflexivity. (* subgoal [0+n = n] *)
reflexivity. (* subgoal [n*m = m*n] *)
Qed.
(*** Remark: the syntax [asserts_rewrite (E1 = E2) in H] allows
rewriting in the hypothesis [H] rather than in the goal. *)
(** The tactic [cuts_rewrite (E1 = E2)] is like
[asserts_rewrite (E1 = E2)], except that the equality [E1 = E2]
appears as first subgoal. *)
Theorem mult_0_plus' : forall n m : nat,
(0 + n) * m = n * m.
Proof.
intros n m.
cuts_rewrite (0 + n = n).
reflexivity. (* subgoal [n*m = m*n] *)
reflexivity. (* subgoal [0+n = n] *)
Qed.
(** More generally, the tactics [asserts_rewrite] and [cuts_rewrite]
can be provided a lemma as argument. For example, one can write
[asserts_rewrite (forall a b, a*(S b) = a*b+a)].
This formulation is useful when [a] and [b] are big terms,
since there is no need to repeat their statements. *)
Theorem mult_0_plus'' : forall u v w x y z: nat,
(u + v) * (S (w * x + y)) = z.
Proof.
intros. asserts_rewrite (forall a b, a*(S b) = a*b+a).
(* first subgoal: [forall a b, a*(S b) = a*b+a] *)
(* second subgoal: [(u + v) * (w * x + y) + (u + v) = z] *)
Abort.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [substs] *)
(** The tactic [substs] is similar to [subst] except that it
does not fail when the goal contains "circular equalities",
such as [x = f x]. *)
Lemma demo_substs : forall x y (f:nat->nat),
x = f x -> y = x -> y = f x.
Proof.
intros. substs. (* the tactic [subst] would fail here *)
assumption.
Qed.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [fequals] *)
(** The tactic [fequals] is similar to [f_equal] except that it
directly discharges all the trivial subgoals produced. Moreover,
the tactic [fequals] features an enhanced treatment of equalities
between tuples. *)
Lemma demo_fequals : forall (a b c d e : nat) (f : nat->nat->nat->nat->nat),
a = 1 -> b = e -> e = 2 ->
f a b c d = f 1 2 c 4.
Proof.
intros. fequals.
(* subgoals [a = 1], [b = 2] and [c = c] are proved, [d = 4] remains *)
Abort.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [applys_eq] *)
(** The tactic [applys_eq] is a variant of [eapply] that introduces
equalities for subterms that do not unify. For example, assume
the goal is the proposition [P x y] and assume we have the
assumption [H] asserting that [P x z] holds. We know that we can
prove [y] to be equal to [z]. So, we could call the tactic
[assert_rewrite (y = z)] and change the goal to [P x z], but
this would require copy-pasting the values of [y] and [z].
With the tactic [applys_eq], we can call [applys_eq H 1], which
proves the goal and leaves only the subgoal [y = z]. The value [1]
given as argument to [applys_eq] indicates that we want an equality
to be introduced for the first argument of [P x y] counting from
the right. The three following examples illustrate the behavior
of a call to [applys_eq H 1], a call to [applys_eq H 2], and a
call to [applys_eq H 1 2]. *)
Axiom big_expression_using : nat->nat. (* Used in the example *)
Lemma demo_applys_eq_1 : forall (P:nat->nat->Prop) x y z,
P x (big_expression_using z) ->
P x (big_expression_using y).
Proof.
introv H. dup.
(* The old proof: *)
assert (Eq: big_expression_using y = big_expression_using z).
admit. (* Assume we can prove this equality somehow. *)
rewrite Eq. apply H.
(* The new proof: *)
applys_eq H 1.
admit. (* Assume we can prove this equality somehow. *)
Abort.
(** If the mismatch was on the first argument of [P] instead of
the second, we would have written [applys_eq H 2]. Recall
that the occurences are counted from the right. *)
Lemma demo_applys_eq_2 : forall (P:nat->nat->Prop) x y z,
P (big_expression_using z) x ->
P (big_expression_using y) x.
Proof.
introv H. applys_eq H 2.
Abort.
(** When we have a mismatch on two arguments, we want to produce
two equalities. To achieve this, we may call [applys_eq H 1 2].
More generally, the tactic [applys_eq] expects a lemma and a
sequence of natural numbers as arguments. *)
Lemma demo_applys_eq_3 : forall (P:nat->nat->Prop) x1 x2 y1 y2,
P (big_expression_using x2) (big_expression_using y2) ->
P (big_expression_using x1) (big_expression_using y1).
Proof.
introv H. applys_eq H 1 2.
(* produces two subgoals:
[big_expression_using x1 = big_expression_using x2]
[big_expression_using y1 = big_expression_using y2] *)
Abort.
End EqualityExamples.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Some Convenient Shorthands *)
(** This section of the tutorial introduces a few tactics
that help make proof scripts shorter and more readable:
- [unfolds] (without argument) for unfolding the head definition,
- [false] for replacing the goal with [False],
- [gen] as a shorthand for [dependent generalize],
- [skip] for skipping a subgoal even if it contains existential variables,
- [sort] for re-ordering the proof context by moving moving all
propositions at the bottom. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [unfolds] *)
Module UnfoldsExample.
Require Import Hoare.
(** The tactic [unfolds] (without any argument) unfolds the
head constant of the goal. This tactic saves the need to
name the constant explicitly. *)
Lemma bexp_eval_true : forall b st,
beval st b = true -> (bassn b) st.
Proof.
intros b st Hbe. dup.
(* The old proof: *)
unfold bassn. assumption.
(* The new proof: *)
unfolds. assumption.
Qed.
(** Remark: contrary to the tactic [hnf], which may unfold several
constants, [unfolds] performs only a single step of unfolding. *)
(** Remark: the tactic [unfolds in H] can be used to unfold the
head definition of the hypothesis [H]. *)
End UnfoldsExample.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactics [false] and [tryfalse] *)
(** The tactic [false] can be used to replace any goal with [False].
In short, it is a shorthand for [exfalso].
Moreover, [false] proves the goal if it contains an absurd
assumption, such as [False] or [0 = S n], or if it contains
contradictory assumptions, such as [x = true] and [x = false]. *)
Lemma demo_false :
forall n, S n = 1 -> n = 0.
Proof.
intros. destruct n. reflexivity. false.
Qed.
(** The tactic [false] can be given an argument: [false H] replace
the goals with [False] and then applies [H]. *)
Lemma demo_false_arg :
(forall n, n < 0 -> False) -> (3 < 0) -> 4 < 0.
Proof.
intros H L. false H. apply L.
Qed.
(** The tactic [tryfalse] is a shorthand for [try solve [false]]:
it tries to find a contradiction in the goal. The tactic
[tryfalse] is generally called after a case analysis. *)
Lemma demo_tryfalse :
forall n, S n = 1 -> n = 0.
Proof.
intros. destruct n; tryfalse. reflexivity.
Qed.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [gen] *)
(** The tactic [gen] is a shortand for [generalize dependent]
that accepts several arguments at once. An invokation of
this tactic takes the form [gen x y z]. *)
Module GenExample.
Require Import Stlc.
Import STLC.
Lemma substitution_preserves_typing : forall Gamma x U v t S,
has_type (update Gamma x U) t S ->
has_type empty v U ->
has_type Gamma ([x:=v]t) S.
Proof.
dup.
(* The old proof: *)
intros Gamma x U v t S Htypt Htypv.
generalize dependent S. generalize dependent Gamma.
induction t; intros; simpl.
admit. admit. admit. admit. admit. admit.
(* The new proof: *)
introv Htypt Htypv. gen S Gamma.
induction t; intros; simpl.
admit. admit. admit. admit. admit. admit.
Abort.
End GenExample.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactics [skip], [skip_rewrite] and [skip_goal] *)
(** Temporarily admitting a given subgoal is very useful when
constructing proofs. It gives the ability to focus first
on the most interesting cases of a proof. The tactic [skip]
is like [admit] except that it also works when the proof
includes existential variables. Recall that existential
variables are those whose name starts with a question mark,
(e.g., [?24]), and which are typically introduced by [eapply]. *)
Module SkipExample.
Require Import Stlc.
Import STLC.
Example astep_example1 :
(APlus (ANum 3) (AMult (ANum 3) (ANum 4))) / empty_state ==>a* (ANum 15).
Proof.
eapply multi_step. skip. (* the tactic [admit] would not work here *)
eapply multi_step. skip. skip.
(* Note that because some unification variables have
not been instantiated, we still need to write
[Abort] instead of [Qed] at the end of the proof. *)
Abort.
(** The tactic [skip H: P] adds the hypothesis [H: P] to the context,
without checking whether the proposition [P] is true.
It is useful for exploiting a fact and postponing its proof.
Note: [skip H: P] is simply a shorthand for [assert (H:P). skip.] *)
Theorem demo_skipH : True.
Proof.
skip H: (forall n m : nat, (0 + n) * m = n * m).
Abort.
(** The tactic [skip_rewrite (E1 = E2)] replaces [E1] with [E2] in
the goal, without checking that [E1] is actually equal to [E2]. *)
Theorem mult_0_plus : forall n m : nat,
(0 + n) * m = n * m.
Proof.
dup.
(* The old proof: *)
intros n m.
assert (H: 0 + n = n). skip. rewrite -> H.
reflexivity.
(* The new proof: *)
intros n m.
skip_rewrite (0 + n = n).
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Remark: the tactic [skip_rewrite] can in fact be given a lemma
statement as argument, in the same way as [asserts_rewrite]. *)
(** The tactic [skip_goal] adds the current goal as hypothesis.
This cheat is useful to set up the structure of a proof by
induction without having to worry about the induction hypothesis
being applied only to smaller arguments. Using [skip_goal], one
can construct a proof in two steps: first, check that the main
arguments go through without waisting time on fixing the details
of the induction hypotheses; then, focus on fixing the invokations
of the induction hypothesis. *)
Theorem ceval_deterministic: forall c st st1 st2,
c / st \\ st1 ->
c / st \\ st2 ->
st1 = st2.
Proof.
(* The tactic [skip_goal] creates an hypothesis called [IH]
asserting that the statment of [ceval_deterministic] is true. *)
skip_goal.
(* Of course, if we call [assumption] here, then the goal is solved
right away, but the point is to do the proof and use [IH]
only at the places where we need an induction hypothesis. *)
introv E1 E2. gen st2.
(induction E1); introv E2; inverts E2 as.
- (* E_Skip *) reflexivity.
- (* E_Ass *)
subst n.
reflexivity.
- (* E_Seq *)
intros st3 Red1 Red2.
assert (st' = st3) as EQ1.
{ (* Proof of assertion *)
(* was: [apply IHE1_1; assumption.] *)
(* new: *) eapply IH. eapply E1_1. eapply Red1. }
subst st3.
(* was: apply IHE1_2. assumption.] *)
(* new: *) eapply IH. eapply E1_2. eapply Red2.
(* The other cases are similiar. *)
Abort.
End SkipExample.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The Tactic [sort] *)
Module SortExamples.
Require Import Imp.
(** The tactic [sort] reorganizes the proof context by placing
all the variables at the top and all the hypotheses at the
bottom, thereby making the proof context more readable. *)
Theorem ceval_deterministic: forall c st st1 st2,
c / st \\ st1 ->
c / st \\ st2 ->
st1 = st2.
Proof.
intros c st st1 st2 E1 E2.
generalize dependent st2.
(induction E1); intros st2 E2; inverts E2.
admit. admit. (* Skipping some trivial cases *)
sort. (* Observe how the context is reorganized *)
Abort.
End SortExamples.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Tactics for Advanced Lemma Instantiation *)
(** This last section describes a mechanism for instantiating a lemma
by providing some of its arguments and leaving other implicit.
Variables whose instantiation is not provided are turned into
existentential variables, and facts whose instantiation is not
provided are turned into subgoals.
Remark: this instantion mechanism goes far beyond the abilities of
the "Implicit Arguments" mechanism. The point of the instantiation
mechanism described in this section is that you will no longer need
to spend time figuring out how many underscore symbols you need to
write. *)
(** In this section, we'll use a useful feature of Coq for decomposing
conjunctions and existentials. In short, a tactic like [intros] or
[destruct] can be provided with a pattern [(H1 & H2 & H3 & H4 & H5)],
which is a shorthand for [[H1 [H2 [H3 [H4 H5]]]]]]. For example,
[destruct (H _ _ _ Htypt) as [T [Hctx Hsub]].] can be rewritten in
the form [destruct (H _ _ _ Htypt) as (T & Hctx & Hsub).] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Working of [lets] *)
(** When we have a lemma (or an assumption) that we want to exploit,
we often need to explicitly provide arguments to this lemma,
writing something like:
[destruct (typing_inversion_var _ _ _ Htypt) as (T & Hctx & Hsub).]
The need to write several times the "underscore" symbol is tedious.
Not only we need to figure out how many of them to write down, but
it also makes the proof scripts look prettly ugly. With the tactic
[lets], one can simply write:
[lets (T & Hctx & Hsub): typing_inversion_var Htypt.]
In short, this tactic [lets] allows to specialize a lemma on a bunch
of variables and hypotheses. The syntax is [lets I: E0 E1 .. EN],
for building an hypothesis named [I] by applying the fact [E0] to the
arguments [E1] to [EN]. Not all the arguments need to be provided,
however the arguments that are provided need to be provided in the
correct order. The tactic relies on a first-match algorithm based on
types in order to figure out how the to instantiate the lemma with
the arguments provided. *)
Module ExamplesLets.
Require Import Sub.
(* To illustrate the working of [lets], assume that we want to
exploit the following lemma. *)
Axiom typing_inversion_var : forall (G:context) (x:id) (T:ty),
has_type G (tvar x) T ->
exists S, G x = Some S /\ subtype S T.
(** First, assume we have an assumption [H] with the type of the form
[has_type G (tvar x) T]. We can obtain the conclusion of the
lemma [typing_inversion_var] by invoking the tactics
[lets K: typing_inversion_var H], as shown next. *)
Lemma demo_lets_1 : forall (G:context) (x:id) (T:ty),
has_type G (tvar x) T -> True.
Proof.
intros G x T H. dup.
(* step-by-step: *)
lets K: typing_inversion_var H.
destruct K as (S & Eq & Sub).
admit.
(* all-at-once: *)
lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var H.
admit.
Abort.
(** Assume now that we know the values of [G], [x] and [T] and we
want to obtain [S], and have [has_type G (tvar x) T] be produced
as a subgoal. To indicate that we want all the remaining arguments
of [typing_inversion_var] to be produced as subgoals, we use a
triple-underscore symbol [___]. (We'll later introduce a shorthand
tactic called [forwards] to avoid writing triple underscores.) *)
Lemma demo_lets_2 : forall (G:context) (x:id) (T:ty), True.
Proof.
intros G x T.
lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var G x T ___.
Abort.
(** Usually, there is only one context [G] and one type [T] that are
going to be suitable for proving [has_type G (tvar x) T], so
we don't really need to bother giving [G] and [T] explicitly.
It suffices to call [lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var x].
The variables [G] and [T] are then instantiated using existential
variables. *)
Lemma demo_lets_3 : forall (x:id), True.
Proof.
intros x.
lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var x ___.
Abort.
(** We may go even further by not giving any argument to instantiate
[typing_inversion_var]. In this case, three unification variables
are introduced. *)
Lemma demo_lets_4 : True.
Proof.
lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var ___.
Abort.
(** Note: if we provide [lets] with only the name of the lemma as
argument, it simply adds this lemma in the proof context, without
trying to instantiate any of its arguments. *)
Lemma demo_lets_5 : True.
Proof.
lets H: typing_inversion_var.
Abort.
(** A last useful feature of [lets] is the double-underscore symbol,
which allows skipping an argument when several arguments have
the same type. In the following example, our assumption quantifies
over two variables [n] and [m], both of type [nat]. We would like
[m] to be instantiated as the value [3], but without specifying a
value for [n]. This can be achieved by writting [lets K: H __ 3]. *)
Lemma demo_lets_underscore :
(forall n m, n <= m -> n < m+1) -> True.
Proof.
intros H.
(* If we do not use a double underscore, the first argument,
which is [n], gets instantiated as 3. *)
lets K: H 3. (* gives [K] of type [forall m, 3 <= m -> 3 < m+1] *)
clear K.
(* The double underscore preceeding [3] indicates that we want
to skip a value that has the type [nat] (because [3] has
the type [nat]). So, the variable [m] gets instiated as [3]. *)
lets K: H __ 3. (* gives [K] of type [?X <= 3 -> ?X < 3+1] *)
clear K.
Abort.
(** Note: one can write [lets: E0 E1 E2] in place of [lets H: E0 E1 E2].
In this case, the name [H] is chosen arbitrarily.
Note: the tactics [lets] accepts up to five arguments. Another
syntax is available for providing more than five arguments.
It consists in using a list introduced with the special symbol [>>],
for example [lets H: (>> E0 E1 E2 E3 E4 E5 E6 E7 E8 E9 10)]. *)
End ExamplesLets.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Working of [applys], [forwards] and [specializes] *)
(** The tactics [applys], [forwards] and [specializes] are
shorthand that may be used in place of [lets] to perform
specific tasks.
- [forwards] is a shorthand for instantiating all the arguments
of a lemma. More precisely, [forwards H: E0 E1 E2 E3] is the
same as [lets H: E0 E1 E2 E3 ___], where the triple-underscore
has the same meaning as explained earlier on.
- [applys] allows building a lemma using the advanced instantion
mode of [lets], and then apply that lemma right away. So,
[applys E0 E1 E2 E3] is the same as [lets H: E0 E1 E2 E3]
followed with [eapply H] and then [clear H].
- [specializes] is a shorthand for instantiating in-place
an assumption from the context with particular arguments.
More precisely, [specializes H E0 E1] is the same as
[lets H': H E0 E1] followed with [clear H] and [rename H' into H].
Examples of use of [applys] appear further on. Several examples of
use of [forwards] can be found in the tutorial chapter [UseAuto]. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Example of Instantiations *)
Module ExamplesInstantiations.
Require Import Sub.
(** The following proof shows several examples where [lets] is used
instead of [destruct], as well as examples where [applys] is used
instead of [apply]. The proof also contains some holes that you
need to fill in as an exercise. *)
Lemma substitution_preserves_typing : forall Gamma x U v t S,
has_type (update Gamma x U) t S ->
has_type empty v U ->
has_type Gamma ([x:=v]t) S.
Proof with eauto.
intros Gamma x U v t S Htypt Htypv.
generalize dependent S. generalize dependent Gamma.
(induction t); intros; simpl.
- (* tvar *)
rename i into y.
(* An example where [destruct] is replaced with [lets]. *)
(* old: destruct (typing_inversion_var _ _ _ Htypt) as [T [Hctx Hsub]].*)
(* new: *) lets (T&Hctx&Hsub): typing_inversion_var Htypt.
unfold update, t_update in Hctx.
destruct (beq_idP x y)...
+ (* x=y *)
subst.
inversion Hctx; subst. clear Hctx.
apply context_invariance with empty...
intros x Hcontra.
(* A more involved example. *)
(* old: destruct (free_in_context _ _ S empty Hcontra)
as [T' HT']... *)
(* new: *)
lets [T' HT']: free_in_context S (@empty ty) Hcontra...
inversion HT'.
- (* tapp *)
(* Exercise: replace the following [destruct] with a [lets]. *)
(* old: destruct (typing_inversion_app _ _ _ _ Htypt)
as [T1 [Htypt1 Htypt2]]. eapply T_App... *)
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
- (* tabs *)
rename i into y. rename t into T1.
(* Here is another example of using [lets]. *)
(* old: destruct (typing_inversion_abs _ _ _ _ _ Htypt). *)