-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Basics.v
1233 lines (1003 loc) · 44.8 KB
/
Basics.v
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
(**` * Basics: Functional Programming in Coq *)
(* REMINDER:
#####################################################
### PLEASE DO NOT DISTRIBUTE SOLUTIONS PUBLICLY ###
#####################################################
(See the [Preface] for why.)
*)
(* [Admitted] is Coq's "escape hatch" that says accept this definition
without proof. We use it to mark the 'holes' in the development
that should be completed as part of your homework exercises. In
practice, [Admitted] is useful when you're incrementally developing
large proofs. *)
Definition admit {T: Type} : T. Admitted.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Introduction *)
(** The functional programming style brings programming closer to
simple, everyday mathematics: If a procedure or method has no side
effects, then (ignoring efficiency) all we need to understand
about it is how it maps inputs to outputs -- that is, we can think
of it as just a concrete method for computing a mathematical
function. This is one sense of the word "functional" in
"functional programming." The direct connection between programs
and simple mathematical objects supports both formal correctness
proofs and sound informal reasoning about program behavior.
The other sense in which functional programming is "functional" is
that it emphasizes the use of functions (or methods) as
_first-class_ values -- i.e., values that can be passed as
arguments to other functions, returned as results, included in
data structures, etc. The recognition that functions can be
treated as data in this way enables a host of useful and powerful
idioms.
Other common features of functional languages include _algebraic
data types_ and _pattern matching_, which make it easy to
construct and manipulate rich data structures, and sophisticated
_polymorphic type systems_ supporting abstraction and code reuse.
Coq shares all of these features.
The first half of this chapter introduces the most essential
elements of Coq's functional programming language. The second
half introduces some basic _tactics_ that can be used to prove
simple properties of Coq programs. *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Enumerated Types *)
(** One unusual aspect of Coq is that its set of built-in
features is _extremely_ small. For example, instead of providing
the usual palette of atomic data types (booleans, integers,
strings, etc.), Coq offers a powerful mechanism for defining new
data types from scratch, from which all these familiar types arise
as instances.
Naturally, the Coq distribution comes with an extensive standard
library providing definitions of booleans, numbers, and many
common data structures like lists and hash tables. But there is
nothing magic or primitive about these library definitions. To
illustrate this, we will explicitly recapitulate all the
definitions we need in this course, rather than just getting them
implicitly from the library.
To see how this definition mechanism works, let's start with a
very simple example. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Days of the Week *)
(** The following declaration tells Coq that we are defining
a new set of data values -- a _type_. *)
Inductive day : Type :=
| monday : day
| tuesday : day
| wednesday : day
| thursday : day
| friday : day
| saturday : day
| sunday : day.
(** The type is called [day], and its members are [monday],
[tuesday], etc. The second and following lines of the definition
can be read "[monday] is a [day], [tuesday] is a [day], etc."
Having defined [day], we can write functions that operate on
days. *)
Definition next_weekday (d:day) : day :=
match d with
| monday => tuesday
| tuesday => wednesday
| wednesday => thursday
| thursday => friday
| friday => monday
| saturday => monday
| sunday => monday
end.
(** One thing to note is that the argument and return types of
this function are explicitly declared. Like most functional
programming languages, Coq can often figure out these types for
itself when they are not given explicitly -- i.e., it performs
_type inference_ -- but we'll include them to make reading
easier. *)
(** Having defined a function, we should check that it works on
some examples. There are actually three different ways to do this
in Coq.
First, we can use the command [Compute] to evaluate a compound
expression involving [next_weekday]. *)
Compute (next_weekday friday).
(* ==> monday : day *)
Compute (next_weekday (next_weekday saturday)).
(* ==> tuesday : day *)
(** (We show Coq's responses in comments, but, if you have a
computer handy, this would be an excellent moment to fire up the
Coq interpreter under your favorite IDE -- either CoqIde or Proof
General -- and try this for yourself. Load this file, [Basics.v],
from the book's accompanying Coq sources, find the above example,
submit it to Coq, and observe the result.)
Second, we can record what we _expect_ the result to be in the
form of a Coq example: *)
Example test_next_weekday:
(next_weekday (next_weekday saturday)) = tuesday.
(** This declaration does two things: it makes an
assertion (that the second weekday after [saturday] is [tuesday]),
and it gives the assertion a name that can be used to refer to it
later.
Having made the assertion, we can also ask Coq to verify it, like
this: *)
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** The details are not important for now (we'll come back to
them in a bit), but essentially this can be read as "The assertion
we've just made can be proved by observing that both sides of the
equality evaluate to the same thing, after some simplification."
Third, we can ask Coq to _extract_, from our [Definition], a
program in some other, more conventional, programming
language (OCaml, Scheme, or Haskell) with a high-performance
compiler. This facility is very interesting, since it gives us a
way to construct _fully certified_ programs in mainstream
languages. Indeed, this is one of the main uses for which Coq was
developed. We'll come back to this topic in later chapters. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Booleans *)
(** In a similar way, we can define the standard type [bool] of
booleans, with members [true] and [false]. *)
Inductive bool : Type :=
| true : bool
| false : bool.
(** Although we are rolling our own booleans here for the sake
of building up everything from scratch, Coq does, of course,
provide a default implementation of the booleans in its standard
library, together with a multitude of useful functions and
lemmas. (Take a look at [Coq.Init.Datatypes] in the Coq library
documentation if you're interested.) Whenever possible, we'll
name our own definitions and theorems so that they exactly
coincide with the ones in the standard library.
Functions over booleans can be defined in the same way as
above: *)
Definition negb (b:bool) : bool :=
match b with
| true => false
| false => true
end.
Definition andb (b1:bool) (b2:bool) : bool :=
match b1 with
| true => b2
| false => false
end.
Definition orb (b1:bool) (b2:bool) : bool :=
match b1 with
| true => true
| false => b2
end.
(** The last two illustrate Coq's syntax for multi-argument
function definitions. The corresponding multi-argument
application syntax is illustrated by the following four "unit
tests," which constitute a complete specification -- a truth
table -- for the [orb] function: *)
Example test_orb1: (orb true false) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_orb2: (orb false false) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_orb3: (orb false true) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_orb4: (orb true true) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** We can also introduce some familiar syntax for the boolean
operations we have just defined. The [Infix] command defines new,
infix notation for an existing definition. *)
Infix "&&" := andb.
Infix "||" := orb.
Example test_orb5: false || false || true = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** _A note on notation_: In [.v] files, we use square brackets to
delimit fragments of Coq code within comments; this convention,
also used by the [coqdoc] documentation tool, keeps them visually
separate from the surrounding text. In the html version of the
files, these pieces of text appear in a [different font].
The special phrases [Admitted] and [admit] can be used as a
placeholder for an incomplete definition or proof. We'll use them
in exercises, to indicate the parts that we're leaving for you --
i.e., your job is to replace [admit] or [Admitted] with real
definitions or proofs. *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (nandb) *)
(** Remove [admit] and complete the definition of the following
function; then make sure that the [Example] assertions below can
each be verified by Coq. (Remove "[Admitted.]" and fill in each
proof, following the model of the [orb] tests above.) The function
should return [true] if either or both of its inputs are
[false]. *)
Definition nandb (b1:bool) (b2:bool) : bool :=
match b2 with
| true => negb b1
| false => true
end.
Example test_nandb1: (nandb true false) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_nandb2: (nandb false false) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_nandb3: (nandb false true) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_nandb4: (nandb true true) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (andb3) *)
(** Do the same for the [andb3] function below. This function should
return [true] when all of its inputs are [true], and [false]
otherwise. *)
Definition andb3 (b1:bool) (b2:bool) (b3:bool) : bool :=
match b1 with
|true => andb b2 b3
|false => false
end.
Example test_andb31: (andb3 true true true) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_andb32: (andb3 false true true) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_andb33: (andb3 true false true) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_andb34: (andb3 true true false) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** [] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Function Types *)
(** Every expression in Coq has a type, describing what sort of
thing it computes. The [Check] command asks Coq to print the type
of an expression. *)
(** For example, the type of [negb true] is [bool]. *)
Check true.
(* ===> true : bool *)
Check (negb true).
(* ===> negb true : bool *)
(** Functions like [negb] itself are also data values, just like
[true] and [false]. Their types are called _function types_, and
they are written with arrows. *)
Check negb.
(* ===> negb : bool -> bool *)
(** The type of [negb], written [bool -> bool] and pronounced
"[bool] arrow [bool]," can be read, "Given an input of type
[bool], this function produces an output of type [bool]."
Similarly, the type of [andb], written [bool -> bool -> bool], can
be read, "Given two inputs, both of type [bool], this function
produces an output of type [bool]." *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Modules *)
(** Coq provides a _module system_, to aid in organizing large
developments. In this course we won't need most of its features,
but one is useful: If we enclose a collection of declarations
between [Module X] and [End X] markers, then, in the remainder of
the file after the [End], these definitions are referred to by
names like [X.foo] instead of just [foo]. Here, we use this
feature to introduce the definition of the type [nat] in an inner
module so that it does not interfere with the one from the
standard library, which comes with a bit of special notational
magic. *)
Module Playground1.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Numbers *)
(** The types we have defined so far are examples of "enumerated
types": their definitions explicitly enumerate a finite set of
elements. A more interesting way of defining a type is to give a
collection of _inductive rules_ describing its elements. For
example, we can define the natural numbers as follows: *)
Inductive nat : Type :=
| O : nat
| S : nat -> nat.
(** The clauses of this definition can be read:
- [O] is a natural number (note that this is the letter "[O],"
not the numeral "[0]").
- [S] is a "constructor" that takes a natural number and yields
another one -- that is, if [n] is a natural number, then [S n]
is too.
Let's look at this in a little more detail.
Every inductively defined set ([day], [nat], [bool], etc.) is
actually a set of _expressions_. The definition of [nat] says how
expressions in the set [nat] can be constructed:
- the expression [O] belongs to the set [nat];
- if [n] is an expression belonging to the set [nat], then [S n]
is also an expression belonging to the set [nat]; and
- expressions formed in these two ways are the only ones belonging
to the set [nat].
The same rules apply for our definitions of [day] and [bool]. The
annotations we used for their constructors are analogous to the
one for the [O] constructor, indicating that they don't take any
arguments.
These three conditions are the precise force of the [Inductive]
declaration. They imply that the expression [O], the expression
[S O], the expression [S (S O)], the expression [S (S (S O))], and
so on all belong to the set [nat], while other expressions like
[true], [andb true false], and [S (S false)] do not.
We can write simple functions that pattern match on natural
numbers just as we did above -- for example, the predecessor
function: *)
Definition pred (n : nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => O
| S n' => n'
end.
(** The second branch can be read: "if [n] has the form [S n']
for some [n'], then return [n']." *)
End Playground1.
Definition minustwo (n : nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => O
| S O => O
| S (S n') => n'
end.
(** Because natural numbers are such a pervasive form of data,
Coq provides a tiny bit of built-in magic for parsing and printing
them: ordinary arabic numerals can be used as an alternative to
the "unary" notation defined by the constructors [S] and [O]. Coq
prints numbers in arabic form by default: *)
Check (S (S (S (S O)))).
(* ===> 4 : nat *)
Compute (minustwo 4).
(* ===> 2 : nat *)
(** The constructor [S] has the type [nat -> nat], just like the
functions [minustwo] and [pred]: *)
Check S.
Check pred.
Check minustwo.
(** These are all things that can be applied to a number to yield a
number. However, there is a fundamental difference between the
first one and the other two: functions like [pred] and [minustwo]
come with _computation rules_ -- e.g., the definition of [pred]
says that [pred 2] can be simplified to [1] -- while the
definition of [S] has no such behavior attached. Although it is
like a function in the sense that it can be applied to an
argument, it does not _do_ anything at all!
For most function definitions over numbers, just pattern matching
is not enough: we also need recursion. For example, to check that
a number [n] is even, we may need to recursively check whether
[n-2] is even. To write such functions, we use the keyword
[Fixpoint]. *)
Fixpoint evenb (n:nat) : bool :=
match n with
| O => true
| S O => false
| S (S n') => evenb n'
end.
(** We can define [oddb] by a similar [Fixpoint] declaration, but here
is a simpler definition that is a bit easier to work with: *)
Definition oddb (n:nat) : bool := negb (evenb n).
Example test_oddb1: oddb 1 = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_oddb2: oddb 4 = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** (You will notice if you step through these proofs that
[simpl] actually has no effect on the goal -- all of the work is
done by [reflexivity]. We'll see more about why that is shortly.)
Naturally, we can also define multi-argument functions by
recursion. *)
Module Playground2.
Fixpoint plus (n : nat) (m : nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => m
| S n' => S (plus n' m)
end.
(** Adding three to two now gives us five, as we'd expect. *)
Compute (plus 3 2).
(** The simplification that Coq performs to reach this conclusion can
be visualized as follows: *)
(* [plus (S (S (S O))) (S (S O))]
==> [S (plus (S (S O)) (S (S O)))]
by the second clause of the [match]
==> [S (S (plus (S O) (S (S O))))]
by the second clause of the [match]
==> [S (S (S (plus O (S (S O)))))]
by the second clause of the [match]
==> [S (S (S (S (S O))))]
by the first clause of the [match]
*)
(** As a notational convenience, if two or more arguments have
the same type, they can be written together. In the following
definition, [(n m : nat)] means just the same as if we had written
[(n : nat) (m : nat)]. *)
Fixpoint mult (n m : nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => O
| S n' => plus m (mult n' m)
end.
Example test_mult1: (mult 3 3) = 9.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** You can match two expressions at once by putting a comma
between them: *)
Fixpoint minus (n m:nat) : nat :=
match n, m with
| O , _ => O
| S _ , O => n
| S n', S m' => minus n' m'
end.
(** The _ in the first line is a _wildcard pattern_. Writing _ in a
pattern is the same as writing some variable that doesn't get used
on the right-hand side. This avoids the need to invent a bogus
variable name. *)
End Playground2.
Fixpoint exp (base power : nat) : nat :=
match power with
| O => S O
| S p => mult base (exp base p)
end.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (factorial) *)
(** Recall the standard mathematical factorial function:
factorial(0) = 1
factorial(n) = n * factorial(n-1) (if n>0)
Translate this into Coq. *)
Fixpoint factorial (n:nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => 1
| S p => mult n (factorial p)
end.
Example test_factorial1: (factorial 3) = 6.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_factorial2: (factorial 5) = (mult 10 12).
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** [] *)
(** We can make numerical expressions a little easier to read and
write by introducing _notations_ for addition, multiplication, and
subtraction. *)
Notation "x + y" := (plus x y)
(at level 50, left associativity)
: nat_scope.
Notation "x - y" := (minus x y)
(at level 50, left associativity)
: nat_scope.
Notation "x * y" := (mult x y)
(at level 40, left associativity)
: nat_scope.
Check ((0 + 1) + 1).
(** (The [level], [associativity], and [nat_scope] annotations
control how these notations are treated by Coq's parser. The
details are not important, but interested readers can refer to the
optional "More on Notation" section at the end of this chapter.)
Note that these do not change the definitions we've already made:
they are simply instructions to the Coq parser to accept [x + y]
in place of [plus x y] and, conversely, to the Coq pretty-printer
to display [plus x y] as [x + y].
When we say that Coq comes with nothing built-in, we really mean
it: even equality testing for numbers is a user-defined
operation! *)
(** The [beq_nat] function tests [nat]ural numbers for [eq]uality,
yielding a [b]oolean. Note the use of nested [match]es (we could
also have used a simultaneous match, as we did in [minus].) *)
Fixpoint beq_nat (n m : nat) : bool :=
match n with
| O => match m with
| O => true
| S m' => false
end
| S n' => match m with
| O => false
| S m' => beq_nat n' m'
end
end.
(** The [leb] function tests whether its first argument is less than or
equal to its second argument, yielding a boolean. *)
Fixpoint leb (n m : nat) : bool :=
match n with
| O => true
| S n' =>
match m with
| O => false
| S m' => leb n' m'
end
end.
Example test_leb1: (leb 2 2) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_leb2: (leb 2 4) = true.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_leb3: (leb 4 2) = false.
Proof. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (blt_nat) *)
(** The [blt_nat] function tests [nat]ural numbers for [l]ess-[t]han,
yielding a [b]oolean. Instead of making up a new [Fixpoint] for
this one, define it in terms of a previously defined function. *)
Definition blt_nat (n m : nat) : bool :=
(leb n m) && (negb (beq_nat n m)).
Example test_blt_nat1: (blt_nat 2 2) = false.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_blt_nat2: (blt_nat 2 4) = true.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
Example test_blt_nat3: (blt_nat 4 2) = false.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Proof by Simplification *)
(** Now that we've defined a few datatypes and functions, let's
turn to stating and proving properties of their behavior.
Actually, we've already started doing this: each [Example] in the
previous sections makes a precise claim about the behavior of some
function on some particular inputs. The proofs of these claims
were always the same: use [simpl] to simplify both sides of the
equation, then use [reflexivity] to check that both sides contain
identical values.
The same sort of "proof by simplification" can be used to prove
more interesting properties as well. For example, the fact that
[0] is a "neutral element" for [+] on the left can be proved just
by observing that [0 + n] reduces to [n] no matter what [n] is, a
fact that can be read directly off the definition of [plus].*)
Theorem plus_O_n : forall n : nat, 0 + n = n.
Proof.
intros n. simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
(** (You may notice that the above statement looks different in
the [.v] file in your IDE than it does in the HTML rendition in
your browser, if you are viewing both. In [.v] files, we write the
[forall] universal quantifier using the reserved identifier
"forall." When the [.v] files are converted to HTML, this gets
transformed into an upside-down-A symbol.) *)
(** This is a good place to mention that [reflexivity] is a bit
more powerful than we have admitted. In the examples we have seen,
the calls to [simpl] were actually not needed, because
[reflexivity] can perform some simplification automatically when
checking that two sides are equal; [simpl] was just added so that
we could see the intermediate state -- after simplification but
before finishing the proof. Here is a shorter proof of the
theorem: *)
Theorem plus_O_n' : forall n : nat, 0 + n = n.
Proof.
intros n. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Moreover, it will be useful later to know that [reflexivity]
does somewhat _more_ simplification than [simpl] does -- for
example, it tries "unfolding" defined terms, replacing them with
their right-hand sides. The reason for this difference is that,
if reflexivity succeeds, the whole goal is finished and we don't
need to look at whatever expanded expressions [reflexivity] has
created by all this simplification and unfolding; by contrast,
[simpl] is used in situations where we may have to read and
understand the new goal that it creates, so we would not want it
blindly expanding definitions and leaving the goal in a messy
state. *)
(** The form of the theorem we just stated and its proof are
almost exactly the same as the simpler examples we saw earlier;
there are just a few differences.
First, we've used the keyword [Theorem] instead of [Example].
This difference is purely a matter of style; the keywords
[Example] and [Theorem] (and a few others, including [Lemma],
[Fact], and [Remark]) mean exactly the same thing to Coq.
Second, we've added the quantifier [forall n:nat], so that our
theorem talks about _all_ natural numbers [n]. In order to prove
theorems of this form, we need to to be able to reason by
_assuming_ the existence of an arbitrary natural number [n]. This
is achieved in the proof by [intros n], which moves the quantifier
from the goal to a _context_ of current assumptions. In effect, we
start the proof by saying "Suppose [n] is some arbitrary
number..."
The keywords [intros], [simpl], and [reflexivity] are examples of
_tactics_. A tactic is a command that is used between [Proof] and
[Qed] to guide the process of checking some claim we are making.
We will see several more tactics in the rest of this chapter and
yet more in future chapters.
Other similar theorems can be proved with the same pattern. *)
Theorem plus_1_l : forall n:nat, 1 + n = S n.
Proof.
intros n. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem mult_0_l : forall n:nat, 0 * n = 0.
Proof.
intros n. reflexivity. Qed.
(** The [_l] suffix in the names of these theorems is
pronounced "on the left." *)
(** It is worth stepping through these proofs to observe how the
context and the goal change. *)
(** You may want to add calls to [simpl] before [reflexivity] to
see the simplifications that Coq performs on the terms before
checking that they are equal.
Although simplification is powerful enough to prove some fairly
general facts, there are many statements that cannot be handled by
simplification alone. For instance, we cannot use it to prove
that [0] is also a neutral element for [+] _on the right_. *)
Theorem plus_n_O : forall n, n = n + 0.
Proof.
intros n. simpl. (* Doesn't do anything! *)
(** (Can you explain why this happens? Step through both proofs
with Coq and notice how the goal and context change.)
When stuck in the middle of a proof, we can use the [Abort]
command to give up on it for the moment. *)
Abort.
(** The next chapter will introduce _induction_, a powerful
technique that can be used for proving this goal. For the moment,
though, let's look at a few more simple tactics. *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Proof by Rewriting *)
(** This theorem is a bit more interesting than the others we've
seen: *)
Theorem plus_id_example : forall n m:nat,
n = m ->
n + n = m + m.
(** Instead of making a universal claim about all numbers [n] and [m],
it talks about a more specialized property that only holds when [n
= m]. The arrow symbol is pronounced "implies."
As before, we need to be able to reason by assuming the existence
of some numbers [n] and [m]. We also need to assume the hypothesis
[n = m]. The [intros] tactic will serve to move all three of these
from the goal into assumptions in the current context.
Since [n] and [m] are arbitrary numbers, we can't just use
simplification to prove this theorem. Instead, we prove it by
observing that, if we are assuming [n = m], then we can replace
[n] with [m] in the goal statement and obtain an equality with the
same expression on both sides. The tactic that tells Coq to
perform this replacement is called [rewrite]. *)
Proof.
(* move both quantifiers into the context: *)
intros n m.
(* move the hypothesis into the context: *)
intros H.
(* rewrite the goal using the hypothesis: *)
rewrite -> H.
reflexivity. Qed.
(** The first line of the proof moves the universally quantified
variables [n] and [m] into the context. The second moves the
hypothesis [n = m] into the context and gives it the name [H].
The third tells Coq to rewrite the current goal ([n + n = m + m])
by replacing the left side of the equality hypothesis [H] with the
right side.
(The arrow symbol in the [rewrite] has nothing to do with
implication: it tells Coq to apply the rewrite from left to right.
To rewrite from right to left, you can use [rewrite <-]. Try
making this change in the above proof and see what difference it
makes.) *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (plus_id_exercise) *)
(** Remove "[Admitted.]" and fill in the proof. *)
Theorem plus_id_exercise : forall n m o : nat,
n = m -> m = o -> n + m = m + o.
Proof.
intros n m o. intros H1 H2.
rewrite -> H1. rewrite -> H2. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** The [Admitted] command tells Coq that we want to skip trying
to prove this theorem and just accept it as a given. This can be
useful for developing longer proofs, since we can state subsidiary
lemmas that we believe will be useful for making some larger
argument, use [Admitted] to accept them on faith for the moment,
and continue working on the main argument until we are sure it
makes sense; then we can go back and fill in the proofs we
skipped. Be careful, though: every time you say [Admitted] (or
[admit]) you are leaving a door open for total nonsense to enter
Coq's nice, rigorous, formally checked world! *)
(** We can also use the [rewrite] tactic with a previously proved
theorem instead of a hypothesis from the context. If the statement
of the previously proved theorem involves quantified variables,
as in the example below, Coq tries to instantiate them
by matching with the current goal. *)
Theorem mult_0_plus : forall n m : nat,
(0 + n) * m = n * m.
Proof.
intros n m.
rewrite -> plus_O_n.
reflexivity. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars (mult_S_1) *)
Theorem mult_S_1 : forall n m : nat,
m = S n ->
m * (1 + n) = m * m.
Proof.
intros m n H. simpl. rewrite -> H. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Proof by Case Analysis *)
(** Of course, not everything can be proved by simple
calculation and rewriting: In general, unknown, hypothetical
values (arbitrary numbers, booleans, lists, etc.) can block
simplification. For example, if we try to prove the following
fact using the [simpl] tactic as above, we get stuck. *)
Theorem plus_1_neq_0_firsttry : forall n : nat,
beq_nat (n + 1) 0 = false.
Proof.
intros n.
simpl. (* does nothing! *)
Abort.
(** The reason for this is that the definitions of both
[beq_nat] and [+] begin by performing a [match] on their first
argument. But here, the first argument to [+] is the unknown
number [n] and the argument to [beq_nat] is the compound
expression [n + 1]; neither can be simplified.
To make progress, we need to consider the possible forms of [n]
separately. If [n] is [O], then we can calculate the final result
of [beq_nat (n + 1) 0] and check that it is, indeed, [false]. And
if [n = S n'] for some [n'], then, although we don't know exactly
what number [n + 1] yields, we can calculate that, at least, it
will begin with one [S], and this is enough to calculate that,
again, [beq_nat (n + 1) 0] will yield [false].
The tactic that tells Coq to consider, separately, the cases where
[n = O] and where [n = S n'] is called [destruct]. *)
Theorem plus_1_neq_0 : forall n : nat,
beq_nat (n + 1) 0 = false.
Proof.
intros n. destruct n as [| n'].
- reflexivity.
- reflexivity. Qed.
(** The [destruct] generates _two_ subgoals, which we must then
prove, separately, in order to get Coq to accept the theorem. The
annotation "[as [| n']]" is called an _intro pattern_. It tells
Coq what variable names to introduce in each subgoal. In general,
what goes between the square brackets is a _list of lists_ of
names, separated by [|]. In this case, the first component is
empty, since the [O] constructor is nullary (it doesn't have any
arguments). The second component gives a single name, [n'], since
[S] is a unary constructor.
The [-] signs on the second and third lines are called _bullets_,
and they mark the parts of the proof that correspond to each
generated subgoal. The proof script that comes after a bullet is
the entire proof for a subgoal. In this example, each of the
subgoals is easily proved by a single use of [reflexivity], which
itself performs some simplification -- e.g., the first one
simplifies [beq_nat (S n' + 1) 0] to [false] by first rewriting
[(S n' + 1)] to [S (n' + 1)], then unfolding [beq_nat], and then
simplifying the [match].
Marking cases with bullets is entirely optional: if bullets are
not present, Coq simply asks you to prove each subgoal in
sequence, one at a time. But it is a good idea to use bullets.
For one thing, they make the structure of a proof apparent, making
it more readable. Also, bullets instruct Coq to ensure that a
subgoal is complete before trying to verify the next one,
preventing proofs for different subgoals from getting mixed
up. These issues become especially important in large
developments, where fragile proofs lead to long debugging
sessions.
There are no hard and fast rules for how proofs should be
formatted in Coq -- in particular, where lines should be broken
and how sections of the proof should be indented to indicate their
nested structure. However, if the places where multiple subgoals
are generated are marked with explicit bullets at the beginning of
lines, then the proof will be readable almost no matter what
choices are made about other aspects of layout.
This is also a good place to mention one other piece of somewhat
obvious advice about line lengths. Beginning Coq users sometimes
tend to the extremes, either writing each tactic on its own line
or writing entire proofs on one line. Good style lies somewhere
in the middle. One reasonable convention is to limit yourself to
80-character lines.
The [destruct] tactic can be used with any inductively defined
datatype. For example, we use it next to prove that boolean
negation is involutive -- i.e., that negation is its own
inverse. *)
Theorem negb_involutive : forall b : bool,
negb (negb b) = b.
Proof.
intros b. destruct b.
- reflexivity.
- reflexivity. Qed.
(** Note that the [destruct] here has no [as] clause because
none of the subcases of the [destruct] need to bind any variables,
so there is no need to specify any names. (We could also have
written [as [|]], or [as []].) In fact, we can omit the [as]
clause from _any_ [destruct] and Coq will fill in variable names
automatically. This is generally considered bad style, since Coq
often makes confusing choices of names when left to its own
devices.
It is sometimes useful to invoke [destruct] inside a subgoal,
generating yet more proof obligations. In this case, we use
different kinds of bullets to mark goals on different "levels."
For example: *)
Theorem andb_commutative : forall b c, andb b c = andb c b.
Proof.
intros b c. destruct b.
- destruct c.
+ reflexivity.
+ reflexivity.
- destruct c.
+ reflexivity.
+ reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Each pair of calls to [reflexivity] corresponds to the
subgoals that were generated after the execution of the [destruct
c] line right above it. Besides [-] and [+], Coq proofs can also
use [*] (asterisk) as a third kind of bullet. If we ever encounter
a proof that generates more than three levels of subgoals, we can
also enclose individual subgoals in curly braces ([{ ... }]): *)
Theorem andb_commutative' : forall b c, andb b c = andb c b.
Proof.
intros b c. destruct b.
{ destruct c.
{ reflexivity. }
{ reflexivity. } }
{ destruct c.
{ reflexivity. }
{ reflexivity. } }
Qed.
(** Since curly braces mark both the beginning and the end of a
proof, they can be used for multiple subgoal levels, as this
example shows. Furthermore, curly braces allow us to reuse the
same bullet shapes at multiple levels in a proof: *)
Theorem andb3_exchange :
forall b c d, andb (andb b c) d = andb (andb b d) c.
Proof.
intros b c d. destruct b.
- destruct c.
{ destruct d.
- reflexivity.
- reflexivity. }
{ destruct d.
- reflexivity.
- reflexivity. }
- destruct c.
{ destruct d.
- reflexivity.
- reflexivity. }
{ destruct d.
- reflexivity.
- reflexivity. }
Qed.
(** Before closing the chapter, let's mention one final
convenience. As you may have noticed, many proofs perform case
analysis on a variable right after introducing it:
intros x y. destruct y as [|y].
This pattern is so common that Coq provides a shorthand for it: we
can perform case analysis on a variable when introducing it by