Skip to content

Latest commit

 

History

History
1526 lines (1190 loc) · 55.3 KB

tactics.md

File metadata and controls

1526 lines (1190 loc) · 55.3 KB

Mathlib tactics

In addition to the tactics found in the core library, mathlib provides a number of specific interactive tactics. Here we document the mostly commonly used ones, as well as some underdocumented tactics from core.

cc (congruence closure)

The congruence closure tactic cc tries to solve the goal by chaining equalities from context and applying congruence (ie if a = b then f a = f b). It is a finishing tactic, ie is meant to close the current goal, not to make some inconclusive progress. A mostly trivial example would be:

example (a b c : ℕ) (f : ℕ → ℕ) (h: a = b) (h' : b = c) : f a = f c := by cc

As an example requiring some thinking to do by hand, consider:

example (f : ℕ → ℕ) (x : ℕ)
  (H1 : f (f (f x)) = x) (H2 : f (f (f (f (f x)))) = x) :
  f x = x :=
by cc

The tactic works by building an equality matching graph. It's a graph where the vertices are terms and they are linked by edges if they are known to be equal. Once you've added all the equalities in your context, you take the transitive closure of the graph and, for each connected component (i.e. equivalence class) you can elect a term that will represent the whole class and store proofs that the other elements are equal to it. You then take the transitive closure of these equalities under the congruence lemmas.

The cc implementation in Lean does a few more tricks: for example it derives a=b from nat.succ a = nat.succ b, and nat.succ a != nat.zero for any a.

tfae

The tfae tactic suite is a set of tactics that help with proving that certain propositions are equivalent. In data/list/basic.lean there is a section devoted to propositions of the form

tfae [p1, p2, ..., pn]

where p1, p2, through, pn are terms of type Prop. This proposition asserts that all the pi are pairwise equivalent. There are results that allow to extract the equivalence of two propositions pi and pj.

To prove a goal of the form tfae [p1, p2, ..., pn], there are two tactics. The first tactic is tfae_have. As an argument it takes an expression of the form i arrow j, where i and j are two positive natural numbers, and arrow is an arrow such as , ->, , <-, , or <->. The tactic tfae_have : i arrow j sets up a subgoal in which the user has to prove the equivalence (or implication) of pi and pj.

The remaining tactic, tfae_finish, is a finishing tactic. It collects all implications and equivalences from the local context and computes their transitive closure to close the main goal.

tfae_have and tfae_finish can be used together in a proof as follows:

example (a b c d : Prop) : tfae [a,b,c,d] :=
begin
  tfae_have : 31,
  { /- prove c → a -/ },
  tfae_have : 23,
  { /- prove b → c -/ },
  tfae_have : 21,
  { /- prove a → b -/ },
  tfae_have : 42,
  { /- prove d ↔ b -/ },
    -- a b c d : Prop,
    -- tfae_3_to_1 : c → a,
    -- tfae_2_to_3 : b → c,
    -- tfae_1_to_2 : a → b,
    -- tfae_4_iff_2 : d ↔ b
    -- ⊢ tfae [a, b, c, d]
  tfae_finish,
end

rcases

The rcases tactic is the same as cases, but with more flexibility in the with pattern syntax to allow for recursive case splitting. The pattern syntax uses the following recursive grammar:

patt ::= (patt_list "|")* patt_list
patt_list ::= id | "_" | "" (patt ",")* patt ""

A pattern like ⟨a, b, c⟩ | ⟨d, e⟩ will do a split over the inductive datatype, naming the first three parameters of the first constructor as a,b,c and the first two of the second constructor d,e. If the list is not as long as the number of arguments to the constructor or the number of constructors, the remaining variables will be automatically named. If there are nested brackets such as ⟨⟨a⟩, b | c⟩ | d then these will cause more case splits as necessary. If there are too many arguments, such as ⟨a, b, c⟩ for splitting on ∃ x, ∃ y, p x, then it will be treated as ⟨a, ⟨b, c⟩⟩, splitting the last parameter as necessary.

rcases also has special support for quotient types: quotient induction into Prop works like matching on the constructor quot.mk.

rcases h : e with PAT will do the same as rcases e with PAT with the exception that an assumption h : e = PAT will be added to the context.

rcases? e will perform case splits on e in the same way as rcases e, but rather than accepting a pattern, it does a maximal cases and prints the pattern that would produce this case splitting. The default maximum depth is 5, but this can be modified with rcases? e : n.

rintro

The rintro tactic is a combination of the intros tactic with rcases to allow for destructuring patterns while introducing variables. See rcases for a description of supported patterns. For example, rintros (a | ⟨b, c⟩) ⟨d, e⟩ will introduce two variables, and then do case splits on both of them producing two subgoals, one with variables a d e and the other with b c d e.

rintro? will introduce and case split on variables in the same way as rintro, but will also print the rintro invocation that would have the same result. Like rcases?, rintro? : n allows for modifying the depth of splitting; the default is 5.

obtain

The obtain tactic is a combination of have and rcases.

obtain ⟨patt⟩ : type,
{ ... }

is equivalent to

have h : type,
{ ... },
rcases h with ⟨patt⟩

The syntax obtain ⟨patt⟩ : type := proof is also supported.

If ⟨patt⟩ is omitted, rcases will try to infer the pattern.

If type is omitted, := proof is required.

simpa

This is a "finishing" tactic modification of simp. It has two forms.

  • simpa [rules, ...] using e will simplify the goal and the type of e using rules, then try to close the goal using e.

    Simplifying the type of e makes it more likely to match the goal (which has also been simplified). This construction also tends to be more robust under changes to the simp lemma set.

  • simpa [rules, ...] will simplify the goal and the type of a hypothesis this if present in the context, then try to close the goal using the assumption tactic.

replace

Acts like have, but removes a hypothesis with the same name as this one. For example if the state is h : p ⊢ goal and f : p → q, then after replace h := f h the goal will be h : q ⊢ goal, where have h := f h would result in the state h : p, h : q ⊢ goal. This can be used to simulate the specialize and apply at tactics of Coq.

rename_var

rename_var old new renames all bound variables named old to new in the goal. rename_var old new at h does the same in hypothesis h. This is meant for teaching bound variables only. Such a renaming should never be relevant to Lean.

example (P : ℕ →  ℕ → Prop) (h : ∀ n, ∃ m, P n m) : ∀ l, ∃ m, P l m :=
begin
  rename_var n q at h, -- h is now ∀ (q : ℕ), ∃ (m : ℕ), P q m,
  rename_var m n, -- goal is now ∀ (l : ℕ), ∃ (n : ℕ), P k n,
  exact h -- Lean does not care about those bound variable names
end

elide/unelide

The elide n (at ...) tactic hides all subterms of the target goal or hypotheses beyond depth n by replacing them with hidden, which is a variant on the identity function. (Tactics should still mostly be able to see through the abbreviation, but if you want to unhide the term you can use unelide.)

The unelide (at ...) tactic removes all hidden subterms in the target types (usually added by elide).

finish/clarify/safe

These tactics do straightforward things: they call the simplifier, split conjunctive assumptions, eliminate existential quantifiers on the left, and look for contradictions. They rely on ematching and congruence closure to try to finish off a goal at the end.

The procedures do split on disjunctions and recreate the smt state for each terminal call, so they are only meant to be used on small, straightforward problems.

  • finish: solves the goal or fails
  • clarify: makes as much progress as possible while not leaving more than one goal
  • safe: splits freely, finishes off whatever subgoals it can, and leaves the rest

All accept an optional list of simplifier rules, typically definitions that should be expanded. (The equations and identities should not refer to the local context.) All also accept an optional list of ematch lemmas, which must be preceded by using.

abel

Evaluate expressions in the language of additive, commutative monoids and groups. It attempts to prove the goal outright if there is no at specifier and the target is an equality, but if this fails, it falls back to rewriting all monoid expressions into a normal form. If there is an at specifier, it rewrites the given target into a normal form.

example {α : Type*} {a b : α} [add_comm_monoid α] : a + (b + a) = a + a + b := by abel
example {α : Type*} {a b : α} [add_comm_group α] : (a + b) - ((b + a) + a) = -a := by abel
example {α : Type*} {a b : α} [add_comm_group α] (hyp : a + a - a = b - b) : a = 0 :=
by { abel at hyp, exact hyp }

norm_num

Normalises numerical expressions. It supports the operations + - * / ^ and % over numerical types such as , , , , , and can prove goals of the form A = B, A ≠ B, A < B and A ≤ B, where A and B are numerical expressions. It also has a relatively simple primality prover.

import data.real.basic

example : (2 : ℝ) + 2 = 4 := by norm_num
example : (12345.2 : ℝ) ≠ 12345.3 := by norm_num
example : (73 : ℝ) < 789/2 := by norm_num
example : 123456789 + 987654321 = 1111111110 := by norm_num
example (R : Type*) [ring R] : (2 : R) + 2 = 4 := by norm_num
example (F : Type*) [linear_ordered_field F] : (2 : F) + 2 < 5 := by norm_num
example : nat.prime (2^13 - 1) := by norm_num
example : ¬ nat.prime (2^11 - 1) := by norm_num
example (x : ℝ) (h : x = 123 + 456) : x = 579 := by norm_num at h; assumption

ring

Evaluate expressions in the language of commutative (semi)rings. Based on Proving Equalities in a Commutative Ring Done Right in Coq by Benjamin Grégoire and Assia Mahboubi.

The variant ring! uses a more aggessive reducibility setting to determine equality of atoms.

ring_exp

Evaluate expressions in commutative (semi)rings, allowing for variables in the exponent.

This tactic extends ring: it should solve every goal that ring can solve. Additionally, it knows how to evaluate expressions with complicated exponents (where ring only understands constant exponents). The variants ring_exp! and ring_exp_eq! use a more aggessive reducibility setting to determine equality of atoms.

For example:

example (n : ℕ) (m : ℤ) : 2^(n+1) * m = 2 * 2^n * m := by ring_exp
example (a b : ℤ) (n : ℕ) : (a + b)^(n + 2) = (a^2 + b^2 + a * b + b * a) * (a + b)^n := by ring_exp
example (x y : ℕ) : x + id y = y + id x := by ring_exp!

field_simp

The goal of field_simp is to reduce an expression in a field to an expression of the form n / d where neither n nor d contains any division symbol, just using the simplifier (with a carefully crafted simpset named field_simps) to reduce the number of division symbols whenever possible by iterating the following steps:

  • write an inverse as a division
  • in any product, move the division to the right
  • if there are several divisions in a product, group them together at the end and write them as a single division
  • reduce a sum to a common denominator

If the goal is an equality, this simpset will also clear the denominators, so that the proof can normally be concluded by an application of ring or ring_exp.

field_simp [hx, hy] is a short form for simp [-one_div_eq_inv, hx, hy] with field_simps

Note that this naive algorithm will not try to detect common factors in denominators to reduce the complexity of the resulting expression. Instead, it relies on the ability of ring to handle complicated expressions in the next step.

As always with the simplifier, reduction steps will only be applied if the preconditions of the lemmas can be checked. This means that proofs that denominators are nonzero should be included. The fact that a product is nonzero when all factors are, and that a power of a nonzero number is nonzero, are included in the simpset, but more complicated assertions (especially dealing with sums) should be given explicitly. If your expression is not completely reduced by the simplifier invocation, check the denominators of the resulting expression and provide proofs that they are nonzero to enable further progress.

The invocation of field_simp removes the lemma one_div_eq_inv (which is marked as a simp lemma in core) from the simpset, as this lemma works against the algorithm explained above.

For example,

example (a b c d x y : ℂ) (hx : x ≠ 0) (hy : y ≠ 0) :
  a + b / x + c / x^2 + d / x^3 = a + x⁻¹ * (y * b / y + (d / x + c) / x) :=
begin
  field_simp [hx, hy],
  ring
end

congr'

Same as the congr tactic, but takes an optional argument which gives the depth of recursive applications. This is useful when congr is too aggressive in breaking down the goal. For example, given ⊢ f (g (x + y)) = f (g (y + x)), congr' produces the goals ⊢ x = y and ⊢ y = x, while congr' 2 produces the intended ⊢ x + y = y + x. If, at any point, a subgoal matches a hypothesis then the subgoal will be closed.

convert

The exact e and refine e tactics require a term e whose type is definitionally equal to the goal. convert e is similar to refine e, but the type of e is not required to exactly match the goal. Instead, new goals are created for differences between the type of e and the goal. For example, in the proof state

n : ℕ,
e : prime (2 * n + 1)
⊢ prime (n + n + 1)

the tactic convert e will change the goal to

⊢ n + n = 2 * n

In this example, the new goal can be solved using ring.

The syntax convert ← e will reverse the direction of the new goals (producing ⊢ 2 * n = n + n in this example).

Internally, convert e works by creating a new goal asserting that the goal equals the type of e, then simplifying it using congr'. The syntax convert e using n can be used to control the depth of matching (like congr' n). In the example, convert e using 1 would produce a new goal ⊢ n + n + 1 = 2 * n + 1.

unfold_coes

Unfold coercion-related definitions

Instance cache tactics

For performance reasons, Lean does not automatically update its database of class instances during a proof. The group of tactics described below helps forcing such updates. For a simple (but very artificial) example, consider the function default from the core library. It has type Π (α : Sort u) [inhabited α], α, so one can use default α only if Lean can find a registered instance of inhabited α. Because the database of such instance is not automatically updated during a proof, the following attempt won't work (Lean will not pick up the instance from the local context):

def my_id (α : Type) : α → α :=
begin
  intro x,
  have : inhabited α := ⟨x⟩,
  exact default α, -- Won't work!
end

However, it will work, producing the identity function, if one replaces have by its variant haveI described below.

  • resetI: Reset the instance cache. This allows any instances currently in the context to be used in typeclass inference.

  • unfreezeI: Unfreeze local instances, which allows us to revert instances in the context

  • introI/introsI: intro/intros followed by resetI. Like intro/intros, but uses the introduced variable in typeclass inference.

  • haveI/letI: have/let followed by resetI. Used to add typeclasses to the context so that they can be used in typeclass inference. The syntax haveI := <proof> and haveI : t := <proof> is supported, but haveI : t, from _ and haveI : t, { <proof> } are not; in these cases use have : t, { <proof> }, resetI directly).

  • exactI: resetI followed by exact. Like exact, but uses all variables in the context for typeclass inference.

hint

hint lists possible tactics which will make progress (that is, not fail) against the current goal.

example {P Q : Prop} (p : P) (h : P → Q) : Q :=
begin
  hint,
  /- the following tactics make progress:
     ----
     solve_by_elim
     finish
     tauto
  -/
  solve_by_elim,
end

You can add a tactic to the list that hint tries by either using

  1. attribute [hint_tactic] my_tactic, if my_tactic is already of type tactic string (tactic unit is allowed too, in which case the printed string will be the name of the tactic), or
  2. add_hint_tactic "my_tactic", specifying a string which works as an interactive tactic.

suggest

suggest lists possible usages of the refine tactic and leaves the tactic state unchanged. It is intended as a complement of the search function in your editor, the #find tactic, and library_search.

suggest takes an optional natural number num as input and returns the first num (or less, if all possibilities are exhausted) possibilities ordered by length of lemma names. The default for num is 50.

For performance reasons suggest uses monadic lazy lists (mllist). This means that suggest might miss some results if num is not large enough. However, because suggest uses monadic lazy lists, smaller values of num run faster than larger values.

An example of suggest in action,

example (n : nat) : n < n + 1 :=
begin suggest, sorry end

prints the list,

Try this: exact nat.lt.base n
Try this: exact nat.lt_succ_self n
Try this: refine not_le.mp _
Try this: refine gt_iff_lt.mp _
Try this: refine nat.lt.step _
Try this: refine lt_of_not_ge _
...

library_search

library_search is a tactic to identify existing lemmas in the library. It tries to close the current goal by applying a lemma from the library, then discharging any new goals using solve_by_elim.

Typical usage is:

example (n m k : ℕ) : n * (m - k) = n * m - n * k :=
by library_search -- Try this: exact nat.mul_sub_left_distrib n m k

library_search prints a trace message showing the proof it found, shown above as a comment. Typically you will then copy and paste this proof, replacing the call to library_search.

solve_by_elim

The tactic solve_by_elim repeatedly applies assumptions to the current goal, and succeeds if this eventually discharges the main goal.

solve_by_elim { discharger := `[cc] }

also attempts to discharge the goal using congruence closure before each round of applying assumptions.

solve_by_elim* tries to solve all goals together, using backtracking if a solution for one goal makes other goals impossible.

By default solve_by_elim also applies congr_fun and congr_arg against the goal.

The assumptions can be modified with similar syntax as for simp:

  • solve_by_elim [h₁, h₂, ..., hᵣ] also applies the named lemmas (or all lemmas tagged with the named attributes).
  • solve_by_elim only [h₁, h₂, ..., hᵣ] does not include the local context, congr_fun, or congr_arg unless they are explicitly included.
  • solve_by_elim [-id_1, ... -id_n] uses the default assumptions, removing the specified ones.

ext1 / ext

  • ext1 id selects and apply one extensionality lemma (with attribute ext), using id, if provided, to name a local constant introduced by the lemma. If id is omitted, the local constant is named automatically, as per intro.

  • ext applies as many extensionality lemmas as possible;

  • ext ids, with ids a list of identifiers, finds extentionality and applies them until it runs out of identifiers in ids to name the local constants.

When trying to prove:

α β : Type,
f g : α → set β
⊢ f = g

applying ext x y yields:

α β : Type,
f g : α → set β,
x : α,
y : β
⊢ y ∈ f x ↔ y ∈ g x

by applying functional extensionality and set extensionality.

A maximum depth can be provided with ext x y z : 3.

The ext attribute

Tag lemmas of the form:

@[ext]
lemma my_collection.ext (a b : my_collection)
  (h : ∀ x, a.lookup x = b.lookup y) :
  a = b := ...

The attribute indexes extensionality lemma using the type of the objects (i.e. my_collection) which it gets from the statement of the lemma. In some cases, the same lemma can be used to state the extensionality of multiple types that are definitionally equivalent.

attribute [ext [(→),thunk,stream]] funext

Those parameters are cumulative. The following are equivalent:

attribute [ext [(→),thunk]] funext
attribute [ext [stream]] funext

and

attribute [ext [(→),thunk,stream]] funext

One removes type names from the list for one lemma with:

attribute [ext [-stream,-thunk]] funext

Also, the following:

@[ext]
lemma my_collection.ext (a b : my_collection)
  (h : ∀ x, a.lookup x = b.lookup y) :
  a = b := ...

is equivalent to

@[ext *]
lemma my_collection.ext (a b : my_collection)
  (h : ∀ x, a.lookup x = b.lookup y) :
  a = b := ...

The * parameter indicates to simply infer the type from the lemma's statement.

This allows us specify type synonyms along with the type that referred to in the lemma statement.

@[ext [*,my_type_synonym]]
lemma my_collection.ext (a b : my_collection)
  (h : ∀ x, a.lookup x = b.lookup y) :
  a = b := ...

Attribute ext can be applied to a structure to generate its extensionality lemma:

@[ext]
structure foo (α : Type*) :=
(x y : ℕ)
(z : {z // z < x})
(k : α)
(h : x < y)

will generate:

@[ext] lemma foo.ext : ∀ {α : Type u_1} (x y : foo α), x.x = y.x → x.y = y.y → x.z == y.z → x.k = y.k → x = y
lemma foo.ext_iff : ∀ {α : Type u_1} (x y : foo α), x = y ↔ x.x = y.x ∧ x.y = y.y ∧ x.z == y.z ∧ x.k = y.k

refine_struct

refine_struct { .. } acts like refine but works only with structure instance literals. It creates a goal for each missing field and tags it with the name of the field so that have_field can be used to generically refer to the field currently being refined.

As an example, we can use refine_struct to automate the construction semigroup instances:

refine_struct ( { .. } : semigroup α ),
-- case semigroup, mul
-- α : Type u,
-- ⊢ α → α → α

-- case semigroup, mul_assoc
-- α : Type u,
-- ⊢ ∀ (a b c : α), a * b * c = a * (b * c)

have_field, used after refine_struct _ poses field as a local constant with the type of the field of the current goal:

refine_struct ({ .. } : semigroup α),
{ have_field, ... },
{ have_field, ... },

behaves like

refine_struct ({ .. } : semigroup α),
{ have field := @semigroup.mul, ... },
{ have field := @semigroup.mul_assoc, ... },

apply_rules

apply_rules hs n applies the list of lemmas hs and assumption on the first goal and the resulting subgoals, iteratively, at most n times. n is optional, equal to 50 by default. hs can contain user attributes: in this case all theorems with this attribute are added to the list of rules.

For instance:

@[user_attribute]
meta def mono_rules : user_attribute :=
{ name := `mono_rules,
  descr := "lemmas usable to prove monotonicity" }

attribute [mono_rules] add_le_add mul_le_mul_of_nonneg_right

lemma my_test {a b c d e : real} (h1 : a ≤ b) (h2 : c ≤ d) (h3 : 0 ≤ e) :
a + c * e + a + c + 0 ≤ b + d * e + b + d + e :=
-- any of the following lines solve the goal:
add_le_add (add_le_add (add_le_add (add_le_add h1 (mul_le_mul_of_nonneg_right h2 h3)) h1 ) h2) h3
by apply_rules [add_le_add, mul_le_mul_of_nonneg_right]
by apply_rules [mono_rules]
by apply_rules mono_rules

h_generalize

h_generalize Hx : e == x matches on cast _ e in the goal and replaces it with x. It also adds Hx : e == x as an assumption. If cast _ e appears multiple times (not necessarily with the same proof), they are all replaced by x. cast eq.mp, eq.mpr, eq.subst, eq.substr, eq.rec and eq.rec_on are all treated as casts.

  • h_generalize Hx : e == x with h adds hypothesis α = β with e : α, x : β;
  • h_generalize Hx : e == x with _ chooses automatically chooses the name of assumption α = β;
  • h_generalize! Hx : e == x reverts Hx;
  • when Hx is omitted, assumption Hx : e == x is not added.

pi_instance

pi_instance constructs an instance of my_class (Π i : I, f i) where we know Π i, my_class (f i). If an order relation is required, it defaults to pi.partial_order. Any field of the instance that pi_instance cannot construct is left untouched and generated as a new goal.

assoc_rewrite

assoc_rewrite [h₀, ← h₁] at ⊢ h₂ behaves like rewrite [h₀, ← h₁] at ⊢ h₂ with the exception that associativity is used implicitly to make rewriting possible.

restate_axiom

restate_axiom makes a new copy of a structure field, first definitionally simplifying the type. This is useful to remove auto_param or opt_param from the statement.

As an example, we have:

structure A :=
(x : ℕ)
(a' : x = 1 . skip)

example (z : A) : z.x = 1 := by rw A.a' -- rewrite tactic failed, lemma is not an equality nor a iff

restate_axiom A.a'
example (z : A) : z.x = 1 := by rw A.a

By default, restate_axiom names the new lemma by removing a trailing ', or otherwise appending _lemma if there is no trailing '. You can also give restate_axiom a second argument to specify the new name, as in

restate_axiom A.a f
example (z : A) : z.x = 1 := by rw A.f

def_replacer

def_replacer foo sets up a stub definition foo : tactic unit, which can effectively be defined and re-defined later, by tagging definitions with @[foo].

  • @[foo] meta def foo_1 : tactic unit := ... replaces the current definition of foo.
  • @[foo] meta def foo_2 (old : tactic unit) : tactic unit := ... replaces the current definition of foo, and provides access to the previous definition via old. (The argument can also be an option (tactic unit), which is provided as none if this is the first definition tagged with @[foo] since def_replacer was invoked.)

def_replacer foo : α → β → tactic γ allows the specification of a replacer with custom input and output types. In this case all subsequent redefinitions must have the same type, or the type α → β → tactic γ → tactic γ or α → β → option (tactic γ) → tactic γ analogously to the previous cases.

tidy

tidy attempts to use a variety of conservative tactics to solve the goals. In particular, tidy uses the chain tactic to repeatedly apply a list of tactics to the goal and recursively on new goals, until no tactic makes further progress.

tidy can report the tactic script it found using tidy?. As an example

example : ∀ x : unit, x = unit.star :=
begin
  tidy? -- Prints the trace message: "intros x, exact dec_trivial"
end

The default list of tactics can be found by looking up the definition of default_tidy_tactics.

This list can be overriden using tidy { tactics := ... }. (The list must be a list of tactic string, so that tidy? can report a usable tactic script.)

linarith

linarith attempts to find a contradiction between hypotheses that are linear (in)equalities. Equivalently, it can prove a linear inequality by assuming its negation and proving false.

In theory, linarith should prove any goal that is true in the theory of linear arithmetic over the rationals. While there is some special handling for non-dense orders like nat and int, this tactic is not complete for these theories and will not prove every true goal.

An example:

example (x y z : ℚ) (h1 : 2*x  < 3*y) (h2 : -4*x + 2*z < 0)
        (h3 : 12*y - 4* z < 0)  : false :=
by linarith

linarith will use all appropriate hypotheses and the negation of the goal, if applicable.

linarith [t1, t2, t3] will additionally use proof terms t1, t2, t3.

linarith only [h1, h2, h3, t1, t2, t3] will use only the goal (if relevant), local hypotheses h1, h2, h3, and proofs t1, t2, t3. It will ignore the rest of the local context.

linarith! will use a stronger reducibility setting to try to identify atoms. For example,

example (x : ℚ) : id x ≥ x :=
by linarith

will fail, because linarith will not identify x and id x. linarith! will. This can sometimes be expensive.

linarith {discharger := tac, restrict_type := tp, exfalso := ff} takes a config object with three optional arguments.

  • discharger specifies a tactic to be used for reducing an algebraic equation in the proof stage. The default is ring. Other options currently include ring SOP or simp for basic problems.
  • restrict_type will only use hypotheses that are inequalities over tp. This is useful if you have e.g. both integer and rational valued inequalities in the local context, which can sometimes confuse the tactic.
  • If exfalso is false, linarith will fail when the goal is neither an inequality nor false. (True by default.)

choose

choose a b h using hyp takes an hypothesis hyp of the form ∀ (x : X) (y : Y), ∃ (a : A) (b : B), P x y a b for some P : X → Y → A → B → Prop and outputs into context a function a : X → Y → A, b : X → Y → B and a proposition h stating ∀ (x : X) (y : Y), P x y (a x y) (b x y). It presumably also works with dependent versions.

Example:

example (h : ∀n m : ℕ, ∃i j, m = n + i ∨ m + j = n) : true :=
begin
  choose i j h using h,
  guard_hyp i := ℕ → ℕ → ℕ,
  guard_hyp j := ℕ → ℕ → ℕ,
  guard_hyp h := ∀ (n m : ℕ), m = n + i n m ∨ m + j n m = n,
  trivial
end

squeeze_simp / squeeze_simpa

squeeze_simp and squeeze_simpa perform the same task with the difference that squeeze_simp relates to simp while squeeze_simpa relates to simpa. The following applies to both squeeze_simp and squeeze_simpa.

squeeze_simp behaves like simp (including all its arguments) and prints a simp only invokation to skip the search through the simp lemma list.

For instance, the following is easily solved with simp:

example : 0 + 1 = 1 + 0 := by simp

To guide the proof search and speed it up, we may replace simp with squeeze_simp:

example : 0 + 1 = 1 + 0 := by squeeze_simp
-- prints:
-- Try this: simp only [add_zero, eq_self_iff_true, zero_add]

squeeze_simp suggests a replacement which we can use instead of squeeze_simp.

example : 0 + 1 = 1 + 0 := by simp only [add_zero, eq_self_iff_true, zero_add]

squeeze_simp only prints nothing as it already skips the simp list.

This tactic is useful for speeding up the compilation of a complete file. Steps:

  1. search and replace simp with squeeze_simp (the space helps avoid the replacement of simp in @[simp]) throughout the file.
  2. Starting at the beginning of the file, go to each printout in turn, copy the suggestion in place of squeeze_simp.
  3. after all the suggestions were applied, search and replace squeeze_simp with simp to remove the occurrences of squeeze_simp that did not produce a suggestion.

Known limitation(s):

  • in cases where squeeze_simp is used after a ; (e.g. cases x; squeeze_simp), squeeze_simp will produce as many suggestions as the number of goals it is applied to. It is likely that none of the suggestion is a good replacement but they can all be combined by concatenating their list of lemmas.

fin_cases

fin_cases h performs case analysis on a hypothesis of the form

  1. h : A, where [fintype A] is available, or
  2. h ∈ A, where A : finset X, A : multiset X or A : list X.

fin_cases * performs case analysis on all suitable hypotheses.

As an example, in

example (f : ℕ → Prop) (p : fin 3) (h0 : f 0) (h1 : f 1) (h2 : f 2) : f p.val :=
begin
  fin_cases p; simp,
  all_goals { assumption }
end

after fin_cases p; simp, there are three goals, f 0, f 1, and f 2.

interval_cases

interval_cases n searches for upper and lower bounds on a variable n, and if bounds are found, splits into separate cases for each possible value of n.

As an example, in

example (n : ℕ) (w₁ : n ≥ 3) (w₂ : n < 5) : n = 3 ∨ n = 4 :=
begin
  interval_cases n,
  all_goals {simp}
end

after interval_cases n, the goals are 3 = 3 ∨ 3 = 4 and 4 = 3 ∨ 4 = 4.

In particular, interval_cases n

  1. inspects hypotheses looking for lower and upper bounds of the form a ≤ n and n < b (although in , , and ℕ+ bounds of the form a < n and n ≤ b are also allowed), and also makes use of lower and upper bounds found via lattice.le_top and lattice.bot_le (so for example if n : ℕ, then the bound 0 ≤ n is found automatically), then
  2. calls fin_cases on the synthesised hypothesis n ∈ set.Ico a b, assuming an appropriate fintype instance can be found for the type of n.

The variable n can belong to any type α, with the following restrictions:

  • only bounds on which expr.to_rat succeeds will be considered "explicit" (TODO: generalise this?)
  • an instance of decidable_eq α is available,
  • an explicit lower bound can be found amongst the hypotheses, or from lattice.bot_le n,
  • an explicit upper bound can be found amongst the hypotheses, or from lattice.le_top n,
  • if multiple bounds are located, an instance of decidable_linear_order α is available, and
  • an instance of fintype set.Ico l u is available for the relevant bounds.

You can also explicitly specify a lower and upper bound to use, as interval_cases using hl hu. The hypotheses should be in the form hl : a ≤ n and hu : n < b, in which case interval_cases calls fin_cases on the resulting fact n ∈ set.Ico a b.

conv

The conv tactic is built-in to lean. Inside conv blocks mathlib currently additionally provides

  • erw,
  • ring and ring2,
  • norm_num, and
  • conv (within another conv). Using conv inside a conv block allows the user to return to the previous state of the outer conv block after it is finished. Thus you can continue editing an expression without having to start a new conv block and re-scoping everything. For example:
example (a b c d : ℕ) (h₁ : b = c) (h₂ : a + c = a + d) : a + b = a + d :=
by conv {
  to_lhs,
  conv {
    congr, skip,
    rw h₁,
  },
  rw h₂,
}

Without conv the above example would need to be proved using two successive conv blocks each beginning with to_lhs.

Also, as a shorthand conv_lhs and conv_rhs are provided, so that

example : 0 + 0 = 0 :=
begin
  conv_lhs { simp }
end

just means

example : 0 + 0 = 0 :=
begin
  conv { to_lhs, simp }
end

and likewise for to_rhs.

mono

  • mono applies a monotonicity rule.
  • mono* applies monotonicity rules repetitively.
  • mono with x ≤ y or mono with [0 ≤ x,0 ≤ y] creates an assertion for the listed propositions. Those help to select the right monotonicity rule.
  • mono left or mono right is useful when proving strict orderings: for x + y < w + z could be broken down into either
    • left: x ≤ w and y < z or
    • right: x < w and y ≤ z
  • mono using [rule1,rule2] calls simp [rule1,rule2] before applying mono.

To use it, first import tactic.monotonicity.

Here is an example of mono:

example (x y z k : ℤ)
  (h : 3 ≤ (4 : ℤ))
  (h' : z ≤ y) :
  (k + 3 + x) - y ≤ (k + 4 + x) - z :=
begin
  mono, -- unfold `(-)`, apply add_le_add
  { -- ⊢ k + 3 + x ≤ k + 4 + x
    mono, -- apply add_le_add, refl
    -- ⊢ k + 3 ≤ k + 4
    mono },
  { -- ⊢ -y ≤ -z
    mono /- apply neg_le_neg -/ }
end

More succinctly, we can prove the same goal as:

example (x y z k : ℤ)
  (h : 3 ≤ (4 : ℤ))
  (h' : z ≤ y) :
  (k + 3 + x) - y ≤ (k + 4 + x) - z :=
by mono*

ac_mono

ac_mono reduces the f x ⊑ f y, for some relation and a monotonic function f to x ≺ y.

ac_mono* unwraps monotonic functions until it can't.

ac_mono^k, for some literal number k applies monotonicity k times.

ac_mono h, with h a hypothesis, unwraps monotonic functions and uses h to solve the remaining goal. Can be combined with * or ^k: ac_mono* h

ac_mono : p asserts p and uses it to discharge the goal result unwrapping a series of monotonic functions. Can be combined with * or ^k: ac_mono* : p

In the case where f is an associative or commutative operator, ac_mono will consider any possible permutation of its arguments and use the one the minimizes the difference between the left-hand side and the right-hand side.

To use it, first import tactic.monotonicity.

ac_mono can be used as follows:

example (x y z k m n : ℕ)
  (h₀ : z ≥ 0)
  (h₁ : x ≤ y) :
  (m + x + n) * z + k ≤ z * (y + n + m) + k :=
begin
  ac_mono,
  -- ⊢ (m + x + n) * z ≤ z * (y + n + m)
  ac_mono,
  -- ⊢ m + x + n ≤ y + n + m
  ac_mono,
end

As with mono*, ac_mono* solves the goal in one go and so does ac_mono* h₁. The latter syntax becomes especially interesting in the following example:

example (x y z k m n : ℕ)
  (h₀ : z ≥ 0)
  (h₁ : m + x + n ≤ y + n + m) :
  (m + x + n) * z + k ≤ z * (y + n + m) + k :=
by ac_mono* h₁.

By giving ac_mono the assumption h₁, we are asking ac_refl to stop earlier than it would normally would.

use

Similar to existsi. use x will instantiate the first term of an or Σ goal with x. It will then try to close the new goal using triv, or try to simplify it by applying exists_prop. Unlike existsi, x is elaborated with respect to the expected type.

use will alternatively take a list of terms [x0, ..., xn].

use will work with constructors of arbitrary inductive types.

Examples:

example (α : Type) : ∃ S : set α, S = S :=
by use ∅

example : ∃ x : ℤ, x = x :=
by use 42

example : ∃ n > 0, n = n :=
begin
  use 1,
  -- goal is now 1 > 0 ∧ 1 = 1, whereas it would be ∃ (H : 1 > 0), 1 = 1 after existsi 1.
  exact ⟨zero_lt_one, rfl⟩,
end

example : ∃ a b c : ℤ, a + b + c = 6 :=
by use [1, 2, 3]

example : ∃ p : ℤ × ℤ, p.1 = 1 :=
by use ⟨1, 42

clear_aux_decl

clear_aux_decl clears every aux_decl in the local context for the current goal. This includes the induction hypothesis when using the equation compiler and _let_match and _fun_match.

It is useful when using a tactic such as finish, simp * or subst that may use these auxiliary declarations, and produce an error saying the recursion is not well founded.

example (n m : ℕ) (h₁ : n = m) (h₂ : ∃ a : ℕ, a = n ∧ a = m) : 2 * m = 2 * n :=
let ⟨a, ha⟩ := h₂ in
begin
  clear_aux_decl, -- subst will fail without this line
  subst h₁
end

example (x y : ℕ) (h₁ : ∃ n : ℕ, n * 1 = 2) (h₂ : 1 + 1 = 2 → x * 1 = y) : x = y :=
let ⟨n, hn⟩ := h₁ in
begin
  clear_aux_decl, -- finish produces an error without this line
  finish
end

set

set a := t with h is a variant of let a := t. It adds the hypothesis h : a = t to the local context and replaces t with a everywhere it can.

set a := t with ←h will add h : t = a instead.

set! a := t with h does not do any replacing.

example (x : ℕ) (h : x = 3)  : x + x + x = 9 :=
begin
  set y := x with ←h_xy,
/-
x : ℕ,
y : ℕ := x,
h_xy : x = y,
h : y = 3
⊢ y + y + y = 9
-/
end

omega

omega attempts to discharge goals in the quantifier-free fragment of linear integer and natural number arithmetic using the Omega test. For instance:

example (x y : int) : (x ≤ 5 ∧ y ≤ 3) → x + y ≤ 8 := by omega

By default, omega tries to guess the correct domain by looking at the goal and hypotheses, and then reverts all relevant hypotheses (i.e., all Props in linear natural number arithmetic, if the domain was determined to be nat) before calling the main procedure (if an hypothesis is not reverted and included in the goal, it will not be available to omega). Therefore, omega will still work with:

example (x y : nat) (h : 2 * x + 1 = 2 * y) : false := by omega

But this behaviour is not always optimal, since it may revert irrelevant hypotheses or incorrectly guess the domain. Use omega manual to disable automatic reverts, and omega int or omega nat to specify the domain.

example (x y z w : int) (h1 : 3 * y ≥ x) (h2 : z > 19 * w) : 3 * x ≤ 9 * y :=
by {revert h1 x y, omega manual}

example (i : int) (n : nat) (h1 : i = 0) (h2 : n < n) : false := by omega nat

example (n : nat) (h1 : n < 34) (i : int) (h2 : i * 9 = -72) : i = -8 :=
by {revert h2 i, omega manual int}

omega handles nat subtraction by repeatedly rewriting goals of the form P[t-s] into P[x] ∧ (t = s + x ∨ (t ≤ s ∧ x = 0)), where x is fresh. This means that each (distinct) occurrence of subtraction will cause the goal size to double during DNF transformation.

omega implements the real shadow step of the Omega test, but not the dark and gray shadows. Therefore, it should (in principle) succeed whenever the negation of the goal has no real solution, but it may fail if a real solution exists, even if there is no integer/natural number solution.

push_neg

This tactic pushes negations inside expressions. For instance, given an assumption

h : ¬ ∀ ε > 0, ∃ δ > 0, ∀ x, |x - x₀| ≤ δ → |f x - y₀| ≤ ε)

writing push_neg at h will turn h into

h : ∃ ε, ε > 0 ∧ ∀ δ, δ > 0 → (∃ x, |x - x₀| ≤ δ ∧ ε < |f x - y₀|),

(the pretty printer does not use the abreviations ∀ δ > 0 and ∃ ε > 0 but this issue has nothing to do with push_neg). Note that names are conserved by this tactic, contrary to what would happen with simp using the relevant lemmas. One can also use this tactic at the goal using push_neg, at every assumption and the goal using push_neg at * or at selected assumptions and the goal using say push_neg at h h' ⊢ as usual.

contrapose

Transforms the goal into its contrapositive.

contrapose turns a goal P → Q into ¬ Q → ¬ P

contrapose! turns a goal P → Q into ¬ Q → ¬ P and pushes negations inside P and Q using push_neg

contrapose h first reverts the local assumption h, and then uses contrapose and intro h

contrapose! h first reverts the local assumption h, and then uses contrapose! and intro h

contrapose h with new_h uses the name new_h for the introduced hypothesis

tautology

This tactic (with shorthand tauto) breaks down assumptions of the form _ ∧ _, _ ∨ _, _ ↔ _ and ∃ _, _ and splits a goal of the form _ ∧ _, _ ↔ _ or ∃ _, _ until it can be discharged using reflexivity or solve_by_elim. This is a finishing tactic: it either closes the goal or raises an error.

The variants tautology! or tauto! use the law of excluded middle.

For instance, one can write:

example (p q r : Prop) [decidable p] [decidable r] : p ∨ (q ∧ r) ↔ (p ∨ q) ∧ (r ∨ p ∨ r) := by tauto

and the decidability assumptions can be dropped if tauto! is used instead of tauto.

norm_cast

This tactic normalizes casts inside expressions. It is basically a simp tactic with a specific set of lemmas to move casts upwards in the expression. Therefore it can be used more safely as a non-terminating tactic. It also has special handling of numerals.

For instance, given an assumption

a b : ℤ
h : ↑a + ↑b < (10 : ℚ)

writing norm_cast at h will turn h into

h : a + b < 10

You can also use exact_mod_cast, apply_mod_cast, rw_mod_cast or assumption_mod_cast. Writing exact_mod_cast h and apply_mod_cast h will normalize the goal and h before using exact h or apply h. Writing assumption_mod_cast will normalize the goal and for every expression h in the context it will try to normalize h and use exact h. rw_mod_cast acts like the rw tactic but it applies norm_cast between steps.

These tactics work with three attributes, elim_cast, move_cast and squash_cast.

elim_cast is for elimination lemmas of the shape Π ..., P ↑a1 ... ↑an = P a1 ... an, for instance:

int.coe_nat_inj' : ∀ {m n : ℕ}, ↑m = ↑n ↔ m = n

rat.coe_int_denom : ∀ (n : ℤ), ↑n.denom = 1

move_cast is for compositional lemmas of the shape Π ..., ↑(P a1 ... an) = P ↑a1 ... ↑an, for instance:

int.coe_nat_add : ∀ (m n : ℕ), ↑(m + n) = ↑m + ↑n`

nat.cast_sub : ∀ {α : Type*} [add_group α] [has_one α] {m n : ℕ}, m ≤ n → ↑(n - m) = ↑n - ↑m

squash_cast is for lemmas of the shape Π ..., ↑↑a = ↑a, for instance:

int.cast_coe_nat : ∀ (n : ℕ), ↑↑n = ↑n

int.cats_id : int.cast_id : ∀ (n : ℤ), ↑n = n

push_cast rewrites the expression to move casts toward the leaf nodes. This uses move_cast lemmas in the "forward" direction. For example, ↑(a + b) will be written to ↑a + ↑b. It is equivalent to simp only with push_cast, and can also be used at hypotheses with push_cast at h.

convert_to

convert_to g using n attempts to change the current goal to g, but unlike change, it will generate equality proof obligations using congr' n to resolve discrepancies. convert_to g defaults to using congr' 1.

ac_change is convert_to followed by ac_refl. It is useful for rearranging/reassociating e.g. sums:

example (a b c d e f g N : ℕ) : (a + b) + (c + d) + (e + f) + g ≤ N :=
begin
  ac_change a + d + e + f + c + g + b ≤ _,
-- ⊢ a + d + e + f + c + g + b ≤ N
end

apply_fun

Apply a function to some local assumptions which are either equalities or inequalities. For instance, if the context contains h : a = b and some function f then apply_fun f at h turns h into h : f a = f b. When the assumption is an inequality h : a ≤ b, a side goal monotone f is created, unless this condition is provided using apply_fun f at h using P where P : monotone f, or the mono tactic can prove it.

Typical usage is:

open function

example (X Y Z : Type) (f : X → Y) (g : Y → Z) (H : injective $ g ∘ f) :
  injective f :=
begin
  intros x x' h,
  apply_fun g at h,
  exact H h
end

swap

swap n will move the nth goal to the front. swap defaults to swap 2, and so interchanges the first and second goals.

rotate

rotate moves the first goal to the back. rotate n will do this n times.

The reassoc attribute

The reassoc attribute can be applied to a lemma

@[reassoc]
lemma some_lemma : foo ≫ bar = baz := ...

and produce

lemma some_lemma_assoc {Y : C} (f : X ⟶ Y) : foo ≫ bar ≫ f = baz ≫ f := ...

The name of the produced lemma can be specified with @[reassoc other_lemma_name]. If simp is added first, the generated lemma will also have the simp attribute.

The reassoc_of function

reassoc_of h takes local assumption h and add a ≫ f term on the right of both sides of the equality. Instead of creating a new assumption from the result, reassoc_of h stands for the proof of that reassociated statement. This prevents poluting the local context with complicated assumptions used only once or twice.

In the following, assumption h is needed in a reassociated form. Instead of proving it as a new goal and adding it as an assumption, we use reassoc_of h as a rewrite rule which works just as well.

example (X Y Z W : C) (x : X ⟶ Y) (y : Y ⟶ Z) (z z' : Z ⟶ W) (w : X ⟶ Z)
  (h : x ≫ y = w)
  (h' : y ≫ z = y ≫ z') :
  x ≫ y ≫ z = w ≫ z' :=
begin
  -- reassoc_of h : ∀ {X' : C} (f : W ⟶ X'), x ≫ y ≫ f = w ≫ f
  rw [h',reassoc_of h],
end

Although reassoc_of is not a tactic or a meta program, its type is generated through meta-programming to make it usable inside normal expressions.

lift

Lift an expression to another type.

  • Usage: 'lift' expr 'to' expr ('using' expr)? ('with' id (id id?)?)?.
  • If n : ℤ and hn : n ≥ 0 then the tactic lift n to ℕ using hn creates a new constant of type , also named n and replaces all occurrences of the old variable (n : ℤ) with ↑n (where n in the new variable). It will remove n and hn from the context.
    • So for example the tactic lift n to ℕ using hn transforms the goal n : ℤ, hn : n ≥ 0, h : P n ⊢ n = 3 to n : ℕ, h : P ↑n ⊢ ↑n = 3 (here P is some term of type ℤ → Prop).
  • The argument using hn is optional, the tactic lift n to ℕ does the same, but also creates a new subgoal that n ≥ 0 (where n is the old variable).
    • So for example the tactic lift n to ℕ transforms the goal n : ℤ, h : P n ⊢ n = 3 to two goals n : ℕ, h : P ↑n ⊢ ↑n = 3 and n : ℤ, h : P n ⊢ n ≥ 0.
  • You can also use lift n to ℕ using e where e is any expression of type n ≥ 0.
  • Use lift n to ℕ with k to specify the name of the new variable.
  • Use lift n to ℕ with k hk to also specify the name of the equality ↑k = n. In this case, n will remain in the context. You can use rfl for the name of hk to substitute n away (i.e. the default behavior).
  • You can also use lift e to ℕ with k hk where e is any expression of type . In this case, the hk will always stay in the context, but it will be used to rewrite e in all hypotheses and the target.
    • So for example the tactic lift n + 3 to ℕ using hn with k hk transforms the goal n : ℤ, hn : n + 3 ≥ 0, h : P (n + 3) ⊢ n + 3 = 2 * n to the goal n : ℤ, k : ℕ, hk : ↑k = n + 3, h : P ↑k ⊢ ↑k = 2 * n.
  • The tactic lift n to ℕ using h will remove h from the context. If you want to keep it, specify it again as the third argument to with, like this: lift n to ℕ using h with n rfl h.
  • More generally, this can lift an expression from α to β assuming that there is an instance of can_lift α β. In this case the proof obligation is specified by can_lift.cond.
  • Given an instance can_lift β γ, it can also lift α → β to α → γ; more generally, given β : Π a : α, Type*, γ : Π a : α, Type*, and [Π a : α, can_lift (β a) (γ a)], it automatically generates an instance can_lift (Π a, β a) (Π a, γ a).

import_private

import_private foo from bar finds a private declaration foo in the same file as bar and creates a local notation to refer to it.

import_private foo, looks for foo in all (imported) files.

When possible, make foo non-private rather than using this feature.

default_dec_tac'

default_dec_tac' is a replacement for the core tactic default_dec_tac, fixing a bug. This bug is often indicated by a message nested exception message: tactic failed, there are no goals to be solved,and solved by appending using_well_founded wf_tacs to the recursive definition. See also additional documentation of using_well_founded in docs/extras/well_founded_recursion.md.

simps

  • The @[simps] attribute automatically derives lemmas specifying the projections of the declaration.
  • Example: (note that the forward and reverse functions are specified differently!)
    @[simps] def refl (α) : α ≃ α := ⟨id, λ x, x, λ x, rfl, λ x, rfl⟩
    derives two simp-lemmas:
    @[simp] lemma refl_to_fun (α) (x : α) : (refl α).to_fun x = id x
    @[simp] lemma refl_inv_fun (α) (x : α) : (refl α).inv_fun x = x
  • It does not derive simp-lemmas for the prop-valued projections.
  • It will automatically reduce newly created beta-redexes, but not unfold any definitions.
  • If one of the fields itself is a structure, this command will recursively create simp-lemmas for all fields in that structure.
  • You can use @[simps proj1 proj2 ...] to only generate the projection lemmas for the specified projections. For example:
    attribute [simps to_fun] refl
  • If one of the values is an eta-expanded structure, we will eta-reduce this structure.
  • You can use @[simps lemmas_only] to derive the lemmas, but not mark them as simp-lemmas.
  • You can use @[simps short_name] to only use the name of the last projection for the name of the generated lemmas.
  • The precise syntax is ('simps' 'lemmas_only'? 'short_name'? ident*).
  • If one of the projections is marked as a coercion, the generated lemmas do not use this coercion.
  • @[simps] reduces let-expressions where necessary.
  • If one of the fields is a partially applied constructor, we will eta-expand it (this likely never happens).

clear'

An improved version of the standard clear tactic. clear is sensitive to the order of its arguments: clear x y may fail even though both x and y could be cleared (if the type of y depends on x). clear' lifts this limitation.

example {α} {β : α → Type} (a : α) (b : β a) : unit :=
begin
  try { clear a b }, -- fails since `b` depends on `a`
  clear' a b,        -- succeeds
  exact ()
end

clear_dependent

A variant of clear' which clears not only the given hypotheses, but also any other hypotheses depending on them.

example {α} {β : α → Type} (a : α) (b : β a) : unit :=
begin
  try { clear' a },  -- fails since `b` depends on `a`
  clear_dependent a, -- succeeds, clearing `a` and `b`
  exact ()
end

simp_rw

simp_rw functions as a mix of simp and rw. Like rw, it applies each rewrite rule in the given order, but like simp it repeatedly applies these rules and also under binders like ∀ x, ..., ∃ x, ... and λ x, ....

Usage:

  • simp_rw [lemma_1, ..., lemma_n] will rewrite the goal by applying the lemmas in that order.
  • simp_rw [lemma_1, ..., lemma_n] at h₁ ... hₙ will rewrite the given hypotheses.
  • simp_rw [...] at ⊢ h₁ ... hₙ rewrites the goal as well as the given hypotheses.
  • simp_rw [...] at * rewrites in the whole context: all hypotheses and the goal.

For example, neither simp nor rw can solve the following, but simp_rw can:

example {α β : Type} {f : α → β} {t : set β} : (∀ s, f '' s ⊆ t) = ∀ s : set α, ∀ x ∈ s, x ∈ f ⁻¹' t :=
by simp_rw [set.image_subset_iff, set.subset_def]

Lemmas passed to simp_rw must be expressions that are valid arguments to simp.

rename'

Renames one or more hypotheses in the context.

example {α β} (a : α) (b : β) : unit :=
begin
  rename' a a',              -- result: a' : α, b  : β
  rename' a' → a,            --         a  : α, b  : β
  rename' [a a', b b'],      --         a' : α, b' : β
  rename' [a' → a, b' → b],  --         a  : α, b  : β
  exact ()
end

Compared to the standard rename tactic, this tactic makes the following improvements:

  • You can rename multiple hypotheses at once.
  • Renaming a hypothesis always preserves its location in the context (whereas rename may reorder hypotheses).