-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Copy pathintroduction.tex
247 lines (216 loc) · 16.1 KB
/
introduction.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
\chapter{INTRODUCTION.}
\lettrine[lines=2]{T}{HE arts and sciences have} become so extensive,
that to facilitate their acquirement is of as much importance as to
extend their boundaries. Illustration, if it does not shorten the time
of study, will at least make it more agreeable. \textsc{This work} has
a greater aim than mere illustration; we do not introduce colours for
the purpose of entertainment, or to amuse \textit{by certain
combinations of tint and form}, but to assist the mind in its
researches after truth, to increase the facilities of instruction, and
to diffuse permanent knowledge. If we wanted authorities to prove the
importance and usefulness of geometry, we might quote every
philosopher since the days of Plato. Among the Greeks, in ancient, as
in the school of Pestalozzi and others in recent times, geometry was
adopted as the best gymnastic of the mind. In fact, Euclid's Elements
have become, by common consent, the basis of mathematical science all
over the civilized globe. But this will not appear extraordinary, if
we consider that this sublime science is not only better calculated
than any other to call forth the spirit of inquity, to elevate the
mind, and to strengthen the reasoning faculties, but also it forms the
best introduction to most of the useful and important vocations of
human life. Arithmetic, land-surveying, mensuration, engineering,
navigation, mechanics, hydrostatics, pneumatics, optics, physical
astronomy, \&c. are all dependent on the propositions of geometry.
Much however depends on the first communication of any science to a
learner, though the best and most easy methods are seldom adopted.
Propositions are placed before a student, who though having a
sufficient understanding, is told just as much about them on entering
at the very threshold of the science, as gives gives him a
prepossession most unfavourable to his future study of this delightful
subject; or the formalitites and paraphernalia of rigour are so
ostentatiously put forward, as almost to hide the reality. Endless and
perplexing repetitions, which do not confer greater exactitude on the
reasoning, render the demonstrations involved and obscure, and conceal
from the view of the student the consecution of evidence.'' Thus an
aversion is created in the mind of the pupil, and a subject so
calculated to improve the reasoning powers, and give the habit of
close thinking, is degraded by a dry and rigid memory, To raise the
curiosity, and to awaken the listless and dormant powers of younger
minds should be the aim of every teacher; but where examples of
excellence are wanting, the attempts to attain it are but few, while
eminence excites attention and produces imitation. The object of this
Work is to introduce a method of teaching geometry, which has been
much approved of by many scientific men in this country, as well as
in France and America. The plan here adopted forcibly appeals to the
eye, the most sensitive and the most comprehensive of our external
organs, and its pre-eminence to imprint it subject on the mind is
supported by the incontrovertible maxim expressed in the well known
words of Horace:-
\begin{quotation}
\noindent\textit{Segnius irritant animos demissa per aurem \\
Qu\`am qu\ae sunt oculis subjecta fidelibus} \\
A feebler impress through the ear is made,\\
Than what is by the faithful eye conveyed.
\end{quotation}
All language consists of representative signs, and those sins are the
best which effect their purposes with the greatest precision and
dispatch. Such for all common purposes are the audible signs called
words, which are still considered as audible, whether addressed
immediately to the ear, or through the medium of letteers to the ete.
Geomerical science, the object of which is to show th erelative
quantities of their parts by a process of reasoning called
Demonstration. This reasoning has been generally carried on by words,
letters, and black or uuncoloured diagrams; but as the use of coloured
symbols, signs and diagrams in the linear arts and sciences, renders
the process of reasoning more precise, and the attainment more
expeditious, they have been in this instance accordingly adopted.
Such is the expedition of this enticing mode of communicating
knowledge, that the Elements of Euclid can be acquired in less than
one third the time usually emploted, and the retention by the memory
is much more permanent; these facts have been ascertained by numerious
experiments made by the invenror, and seveeral orhers who have adopted
his plans. The particularsof which are few and obvious; the letters
annexed to points, lines, or other parts of a diagram are in fact but
arbitrary names, and represent them in the demonstration; instead of
these, the parts being differently colouresd, are made to name
themselves, for their forms in corresponding colours represent them in
the demonstration.
In order to give a better idea of this system, and of the advantages
gained by its adoption, let us take a right angled triangle, and
express some of its properties both by colours and the method
generally employed.
\newcommand{\cab}{
\begin{tikzpicture}[scale=2]
\path[fill=red] (0,0) ++ (0.5,0) arc (0:36:0.5) -- (0,0);
\end{tikzpicture}
}
\newcommand{\abc}{
\begin{tikzpicture}[baseline=-6.0ex,rotate=216,scale=2]
\path[fill=yellow] (0,0) ++ (0.5,0) arc (0:90:0.5) -- (0,0);
\end{tikzpicture}
}
\newcommand{\bca}{
\begin{tikzpicture}[rotate=126,scale=2]
\path[fill=blue] (0,0) ++ (0.5,0) arc (0:54:0.5) -- (0,0);
\end{tikzpicture}
}
\begin{figure}
\begin{tikzpicture}
\coordinate (A) at (0,0);
\coordinate (B) at (3.2,2.4);
\coordinate (C) at (5,0);
\path[fill=red,ultra thick] (A) ++(0.5,0) arc (0:36:0.5) -- (A);
\path[fill=yellow,ultra thick] (B) ++(-90+36:0.5) arc (-90+36:-180+36:0.5) -- (B);
\path[fill=blue,ultra thick] (C) ++(-0.5,0) arc (180:90+36:0.5) -- (C);
\node[below left ] at (A) {$A$};
\node[above ] at (B) {$B$};
\node[below right] at (C) {$C$};
\draw[blue,ultra thick] (A) -- (B);
\draw[red,ultra thick] (B) -- (C);
\draw[yellow,ultra thick] (C) -- (A);
\end{tikzpicture}
\end{figure}
\begin{center}
\textit{Some of the properties of the right angled triangle
\textrm{ABC}, expressed by the method generally employed.}
\end{center}
\begin{enumerate}
\item The angle BAC, together with the angles BCA and ABC are
equal to two right angles, or twice the angle ABC.
\item The angle CAB added to the angle ACB will be equal to
the angle ABC.
\item The angle ABC is greater than either of the
angles BAC or BCA.
\item The angle BCA or the angle CAB is less than the
angle ABC.
\item If from the angle ABC, there be taken the angle BAC,
the remainder will be equal to the angle ACB.
\item The square of AC is equal to the sum of the squares
of AB and BC.
\end{enumerate}
\begin{center}
\textit{The same properties expressed by colouring
the different parts.}
\end{center}
\begin{enumerate}
\item \[ \cab \plus \abc \plus \bca \equals 2\, \abc \equals \rightangles.\]
That is, the red angle added to the yellow angle added to the blue angle, equal twice the yellow angle, equal two right angles.
\item \[\cab \plus \bca \equals \abc.\]
Or in words, the red angle added to the blue angle, equal the yellow angle.
\item \[\abc \greater \cab \text{ or } \greater \bca.\]
The yellow angle is greater than either the red of blue angle.
\item \[\cab \text{ or } \bca \less\abc.\]
Either the red or blue angle is less than the yellow angle.
\item \[\abc \text{ minus } \bca \equals \cab.\]
In other terms, the yellow angle made less by the blue angle equal the red angle.
\item \[\tikzhline[yellow]{1.2cm}^{2} \equals \tikzhline[blue]{1.2cm}^{2} \plus \tikzhline[red]{1.2cm}^{2}.\]
That is, the square of the yellow line is equal to the sum of the squares of the blue and red lines.
\end{enumerate}
In oral demonstrations we gain with colours this important advantage, the
eye and the ear can be addressed at the same moment, so that for teavhing
geometry, and other linear arts and sciences, in classes, the ststem is
the best ever proposed, this is apparent from the examples just
given.
Whence it is evident that a reference from the text to the diagram is more
rapid and sure, by giving the forms and colours of the parts, or by
naming the parts and their colours, than naming the parts and letters on
the diagram. Besides the superior simplicity, this system is likewise
conspicuous for concentration, and wholly excludes the injrious though
prevalent practice of allowing the student to commit the demonstration
to memory; until reason , and fact, and proof only make impressions on
the understanding.
Again, when lecturing on the principles or properties of figures, if we
mention the colour of the part or parts referred to, as in saying, the
red angle, the blue line, or lines, \&c.~the part or parts thus names
will be immediately seen by all in the class at the same instant; not so
if we say the angle ABC, the triangle PFQ, the figure EGKt, and so on;
for the letters must be traces one by one before the students arrange in
their minds the particular magnitude reeferred to, which often occasions
confusino and error, as well as lots of time. Also if the parts which are
given as equal, have the same colours in any diagram, the mind will not
wander from the object before it; that is, such an arrangement presents
an ocular demonstration of the parts to be proved equal, and the learner
retains the data throughout the whole of the reasoning. But whatever may
be the advantages of the present plan, if it be not substituted for, it
can always be made a powerful auxiliary to the other methods, for the
purpose of introduction, or of a more speedt reminiscence, or of more
permanent retention by the memory.
The experience of all who have formed systems to impress facts on the
understanding, agree in proving that coloured representations, as
pictures, cuts, diagrams, \&c.~are more easily fixed in the mind than
mere sentences unmarked by any peculiarity. Curious as it may appear,
poets seem to be aware of this fact more than mathematicians; many modern
poets allude to this visible system of communicating knowledge, one of
them has thus expressed himself:
\begin{quotation}
Sounds which address the ear are lost and die\\
In one short hour, but these which strike the eye,\\
Live long upon the mind, the faithful sight\\
Engraves the knowledge with a beam of light.
\end{quotation}
This perhaps may be reckoned the only improvement on which plain
geometry has recerived since the dats of Euclid, and if there were any
geometers of note before that time, Eclid's success has quite ecliped
their memory, and even occasioned all good things of that kindto be
assigned to him; like \AE sop among the writers of Fables. It may also be
worthy of remark, as tangible diagrams afford only the medium through
which geometry and other linear arts and scoences can be taught to the
blind, this visible system is no less adapted to the exigencies of the
deaf and dumb.
Care must be taken to show that colour has nothing to do with the lines, angles, or magnitudes except merely to name them. A mathematical line, which is length without breadth, cannot possess colour, yet the junction of two colours on the same plane gives a good idea of what is meant by a mathematical linel recorllect we are speaking familiarly, such a junction is to be understood and not the colour,l when we say the black line, the red line or line, \&c.
Colours and coloured diagrams may at first appear a climsy method to convery proper notions of the properties and parts of mathematical figures and magnitudes, however they will be found to afford a means more refined and extensive than any that has been hitherto proposed.
We shall here define a point, a line, and a sufrace, and demonstrate a proposition in order to show the truth of this assertion.
A spoint is that which has position, but not magnitude; or a point is position only, abstracted from the consideration of length, breadth, and thickness. Perhaps the following descriptiobn is better calculated to explain the nature of a mathematical point to those who have no acquired the idea, than the above specious definition.
Let three colours meet and cover a portion of the paper, where the meet is not blue, not is it yellow, not is it red, as it occupes no potion of the plane, for it it did, it would belong to the blue, the red or the yellow part; yet it exists, and has position without magnitude, so that with a little reflection , this junction of three colours on a plane, gives a good idea of a methamtical point.
% DIAGRAM OF A CIRCLE HERE
A line is length withou breadth. With the assistance of colours, nearly inthe same manner as before, and idea of a line may be thus give:--
Let two colours meet and cover a potion of the paper; where the meet is not red, nor is it blue; therefore it cannot have breadth, but only length: from which we can readily form an idea of what is meant by a mathematical line. For the purpose of illustration, one colour differing from the colour of the paper, or plane upon which it is drawn, would have been sufficient; hence in future, if we say the red line, the blue line, or line, \& c. it is the junctions with the plane upon which they are drawn are to be understood.
% DIAGRAM OF A PLANE HERE
Surface is that which has length and breadth without thickness.
When we consider a solid body (PQ), we perceive at once that it has three dimensions, namely:-- length, breadth, and thickness; suppose one part of this solid (PS) to be red, and the other part (QR) yellow, and that the colours be distinct without commingling, the blue surface (RS) which separates these parts, or this is the same thing, that which divides the solid without loss of material, must be without thickness, and only possesses length and breadthl this plainly appears from reasoning, similar to that just employed in defining, or rather describing a point and a line.
% Diagram of a cuboid here
The proposition which we have selected to elucidate the manner in which the principles are applied, is the fifth proposition of the first Book.
%COPY THE FIFTH PROPOSITION.
Our object in this place being to introduce the system rather than to teach any particular set of propositions, we have therefore selected the foregoing out of the regular course. For schools and other public places of instruction, dyed chalks will answer to describe diagrams, \&c. fo rprivate use coloured pencils will be found very convenient.
We are happy to find that the Elements of Mathematics now forms a considerable part of ever found female education, therefore we call the attention of those interested or engaged in the education of ladies to this very attractive mode of communicating knowledge, and to the successing work for its future developement.
We shall for the present conclude by obsercing, as the sensed of sight and hearing can be so forcibly and instantaneously addressed alike with one thousand as with one, \textit{the million} might be taught geometry and other branches of mathematics with great ease, this would advance the purpose of education more than any thing that \textit{might} be names, for it would teach the people how to think, and not what to think; it is in this particular the great error of education originates.