-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Prop.v
1060 lines (816 loc) · 33.1 KB
/
Prop.v
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
(** * Prop: Propositions and Evidence *)
Require Export Logic.
(* ####################################################### *)
(** * Inductively Defined Propositions *)
(** In chapter [Basics] we defined a _function_ [evenb] that tests a
number for evenness, yielding [true] if so. We can use this
function to define the _proposition_ that some number [n] is
even: *)
Definition even (n:nat) : Prop :=
evenb n = true.
(** That is, we can define "[n] is even" to mean "the function [evenb]
returns [true] when applied to [n]."
Note that here we have given a name
to a proposition using a [Definition], just as we have
given names to expressions of other sorts. This isn't a fundamentally
new kind of proposition; it is still just an equality. *)
(** Another alternative is to define the concept of evenness
directly. Instead of going via the [evenb] function ("a number is
even if a certain computation yields [true]"), we can say what the
concept of evenness means by giving two different ways of
presenting _evidence_ that a number is even. *)
Inductive ev : nat -> Prop :=
| ev_0 : ev O
| ev_SS : forall n:nat, ev n -> ev (S (S n)).
(** The first line declares that [ev] is a proposition -- or,
more formally, a family of propositions "indexed by" natural
numbers. (That is, for each number [n], the claim that "[n] is
even" is a proposition.) Such a family of propositions is
often called a _property_ of numbers.
The last two lines declare the two ways to give evidence that a
number [m] is even. First, [0] is even, and [ev_0] is evidence
for this. Second, if [m = S (S n)] for some [n] and we can give
evidence [e] that [n] is even, then [m] is also even, and [ev_SS n
e] is the evidence.
*)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (double_even) *)
Theorem double_even : forall n,
ev (double n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ##################################################### *)
(** For [ev], we had already defined [even] as a function (returning a
boolean), and then defined an inductive relation that agreed with
it. However, we don't necessarily need to think about propositions
first as boolean functions, we can start off with the inductive
definition.
*)
(** As another example of an inductively defined proposition, let's
define a simple property of natural numbers -- we'll call it
"[beautiful]." *)
(** Informally, a number is [beautiful] if it is [0], [3], [5], or the
sum of two [beautiful] numbers.
More pedantically, we can define [beautiful] numbers by giving four
rules:
- Rule [b_0]: The number [0] is [beautiful].
- Rule [b_3]: The number [3] is [beautiful].
- Rule [b_5]: The number [5] is [beautiful].
- Rule [b_sum]: If [n] and [m] are both [beautiful], then so is
their sum. *)
(** We will see many definitions like this one during the rest
of the course, and for purposes of informal discussions, it is
helpful to have a lightweight notation that makes them easy to
read and write. _Inference rules_ are one such notation: *)
(**
----------- (b_0)
beautiful 0
------------ (b_3)
beautiful 3
------------ (b_5)
beautiful 5
beautiful n beautiful m
--------------------------- (b_sum)
beautiful (n+m)
*)
(** *** *)
(** Each of the textual rules above is reformatted here as an
inference rule; the intended reading is that, if the _premises_
above the line all hold, then the _conclusion_ below the line
follows. For example, the rule [b_sum] says that, if [n] and [m]
are both [beautiful] numbers, then it follows that [n+m] is
[beautiful] too. If a rule has no premises above the line, then
its conclusion holds unconditionally.
These rules _define_ the property [beautiful]. That is, if we
want to convince someone that some particular number is [beautiful],
our argument must be based on these rules. For a simple example,
suppose we claim that the number [5] is [beautiful]. To support
this claim, we just need to point out that rule [b_5] says so.
Or, if we want to claim that [8] is [beautiful], we can support our
claim by first observing that [3] and [5] are both [beautiful] (by
rules [b_3] and [b_5]) and then pointing out that their sum, [8],
is therefore [beautiful] by rule [b_sum]. This argument can be
expressed graphically with the following _proof tree_: *)
(**
----------- (b_3) ----------- (b_5)
beautiful 3 beautiful 5
------------------------------- (b_sum)
beautiful 8
*)
(** *** *)
(**
Of course, there are other ways of using these rules to argue that
[8] is [beautiful], for instance:
----------- (b_5) ----------- (b_3)
beautiful 5 beautiful 3
------------------------------- (b_sum)
beautiful 8
*)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (varieties_of_beauty) *)
(** How many different ways are there to show that [8] is [beautiful]? *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(* ####################################################### *)
(** ** Constructing Evidence *)
(** In Coq, we can express the definition of [beautiful] as
follows: *)
Inductive beautiful : nat -> Prop :=
b_0 : beautiful 0
| b_3 : beautiful 3
| b_5 : beautiful 5
| b_sum : forall n m, beautiful n -> beautiful m -> beautiful (n+m).
(** *** *)
(**
The rules introduced this way have the same status as proven
theorems; that is, they are true axiomatically.
So we can use Coq's [apply] tactic with the rule names to prove
that particular numbers are [beautiful]. *)
Theorem three_is_beautiful: beautiful 3.
Proof.
(* This simply follows from the rule [b_3]. *)
apply b_3.
Qed.
Theorem eight_is_beautiful: beautiful 8.
Proof.
(* First we use the rule [b_sum], telling Coq how to
instantiate [n] and [m]. *)
apply b_sum with (n:=3) (m:=5).
(* To solve the subgoals generated by [b_sum], we must provide
evidence of [beautiful 3] and [beautiful 5]. Fortunately we
have rules for both. *)
apply b_3.
apply b_5.
Qed.
(** *** *)
(** As you would expect, we can also prove theorems that have
hypotheses about [beautiful]. *)
Theorem beautiful_plus_eight: forall n, beautiful n -> beautiful (8+n).
Proof.
intros n B.
apply b_sum with (n:=8) (m:=n).
apply eight_is_beautiful.
apply B.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars (b_times2) *)
Theorem b_times2: forall n, beautiful n -> beautiful (2*n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars (b_timesm) *)
Theorem b_timesm: forall n m, beautiful n -> beautiful (m*n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ####################################################### *)
(** * Using Evidence in Proofs *)
(** ** Induction over Evidence *)
(** Besides _constructing_ evidence that numbers are beautiful, we can
also _reason about_ such evidence. *)
(** The fact that we introduced [beautiful] with an [Inductive]
declaration tells Coq not only that the constructors [b_0], [b_3],
[b_5] and [b_sum] are ways to build evidence, but also that these
four constructors are the _only_ ways to build evidence that
numbers are beautiful. *)
(** In other words, if someone gives us evidence [E] for the assertion
[beautiful n], then we know that [E] must have one of four shapes:
- [E] is [b_0] (and [n] is [O]),
- [E] is [b_3] (and [n] is [3]),
- [E] is [b_5] (and [n] is [5]), or
- [E] is [b_sum n1 n2 E1 E2] (and [n] is [n1+n2], where [E1] is
evidence that [n1] is beautiful and [E2] is evidence that [n2]
is beautiful). *)
(** *** *)
(** This permits us to _analyze_ any hypothesis of the form [beautiful
n] to see how it was constructed, using the tactics we already
know. In particular, we can use the [induction] tactic that we
have already seen for reasoning about inductively defined _data_
to reason about inductively defined _evidence_.
To illustrate this, let's define another property of numbers: *)
Inductive gorgeous : nat -> Prop :=
g_0 : gorgeous 0
| g_plus3 : forall n, gorgeous n -> gorgeous (3+n)
| g_plus5 : forall n, gorgeous n -> gorgeous (5+n).
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (gorgeous_tree) *)
(** Write out the definition of [gorgeous] numbers using inference rule
notation.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
[]
*)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (gorgeous_plus13) *)
Theorem gorgeous_plus13: forall n,
gorgeous n -> gorgeous (13+n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** *** *)
(** It seems intuitively obvious that, although [gorgeous] and
[beautiful] are presented using slightly different rules, they are
actually the same property in the sense that they are true of the
same numbers. Indeed, we can prove this. *)
Theorem gorgeous__beautiful_FAILED : forall n,
gorgeous n -> beautiful n.
Proof.
intros. induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = 0". apply b_0.
Case "n = S n'". (* We are stuck! *)
Abort.
(** The problem here is that doing induction on [n] doesn't yield a
useful induction hypothesis. Knowing how the property we are
interested in behaves on the predecessor of [n] doesn't help us
prove that it holds for [n]. Instead, we would like to be able to
have induction hypotheses that mention other numbers, such as [n -
3] and [n - 5]. This is given precisely by the shape of the
constructors for [gorgeous]. *)
(** *** *)
(** Let's see what happens if we try to prove this by induction on the evidence [H]
instead of on [n]. *)
Theorem gorgeous__beautiful : forall n,
gorgeous n -> beautiful n.
Proof.
intros n H.
induction H as [|n'|n'].
Case "g_0".
apply b_0.
Case "g_plus3".
apply b_sum. apply b_3.
apply IHgorgeous.
Case "g_plus5".
apply b_sum. apply b_5. apply IHgorgeous.
Qed.
(* These exercises also require the use of induction on the evidence. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars (gorgeous_sum) *)
Theorem gorgeous_sum : forall n m,
gorgeous n -> gorgeous m -> gorgeous (n + m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (beautiful__gorgeous) *)
Theorem beautiful__gorgeous : forall n, beautiful n -> gorgeous n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, optional (g_times2) *)
(** Prove the [g_times2] theorem below without using [gorgeous__beautiful].
You might find the following helper lemma useful. *)
Lemma helper_g_times2 : forall x y z, x + (z + y) = z + x + y.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem g_times2: forall n, gorgeous n -> gorgeous (2*n).
Proof.
intros n H. simpl.
induction H.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** Here is a proof that the inductive definition of evenness implies
the computational one. *)
Theorem ev__even : forall n,
ev n -> even n.
Proof.
intros n E. induction E as [| n' E'].
Case "E = ev_0".
unfold even. reflexivity.
Case "E = ev_SS n' E'".
unfold even. apply IHE'.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (ev__even) *)
(** Could this proof also be carried out by induction on [n] instead
of [E]? If not, why not? *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(** Intuitively, the induction principle [ev n] evidence [ev n] is
similar to induction on [n], but restricts our attention to only
those numbers for which evidence [ev n] could be generated. *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (l_fails) *)
(** The following proof attempt will not succeed.
Theorem l : forall n,
ev n.
Proof.
intros n. induction n.
Case "O". simpl. apply ev_0.
Case "S".
...
Intuitively, we expect the proof to fail because not every
number is even. However, what exactly causes the proof to fail?
(* FILL IN HERE *)
*)
(** [] *)
(** Here's another exercise requiring induction on evidence. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars (ev_sum) *)
Theorem ev_sum : forall n m,
ev n -> ev m -> ev (n+m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ####################################################### *)
(** ** Inversion on Evidence *)
(** Having evidence for a proposition is useful while proving, because we
can _look_ at that evidence for more information. For example, consider
proving that, if [n] is even, then [pred (pred n)] is
too. In this case, we don't need to do an inductive proof. Instead
the [inversion] tactic provides all of the information that we need.
*)
Theorem ev_minus2: forall n, ev n -> ev (pred (pred n)).
Proof.
intros n E.
inversion E as [| n' E'].
Case "E = ev_0". simpl. apply ev_0.
Case "E = ev_SS n' E'". simpl. apply E'. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (ev_minus2_n) *)
(** What happens if we try to use [destruct] on [n] instead of [inversion] on [E]? *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(** *** *)
(** Here is another example, in which [inversion] helps narrow down to
the relevant cases. *)
Theorem SSev__even : forall n,
ev (S (S n)) -> ev n.
Proof.
intros n E.
inversion E as [| n' E'].
apply E'. Qed.
(** ** The Inversion Tactic Revisited *)
(** These uses of [inversion] may seem a bit mysterious at first.
Until now, we've only used [inversion] on equality
propositions, to utilize injectivity of constructors or to
discriminate between different constructors. But we see here
that [inversion] can also be applied to analyzing evidence
for inductively defined propositions.
(You might also expect that [destruct] would be a more suitable
tactic to use here. Indeed, it is possible to use [destruct], but
it often throws away useful information, and the [eqn:] qualifier
doesn't help much in this case.)
Here's how [inversion] works in general. Suppose the name
[I] refers to an assumption [P] in the current context, where
[P] has been defined by an [Inductive] declaration. Then,
for each of the constructors of [P], [inversion I] generates
a subgoal in which [I] has been replaced by the exact,
specific conditions under which this constructor could have
been used to prove [P]. Some of these subgoals will be
self-contradictory; [inversion] throws these away. The ones
that are left represent the cases that must be proved to
establish the original goal.
In this particular case, the [inversion] analyzed the construction
[ev (S (S n))], determined that this could only have been
constructed using [ev_SS], and generated a new subgoal with the
arguments of that constructor as new hypotheses. (It also
produced an auxiliary equality, which happens to be useless here.)
We'll begin exploring this more general behavior of inversion in
what follows. *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (inversion_practice) *)
Theorem SSSSev__even : forall n,
ev (S (S (S (S n)))) -> ev n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** The [inversion] tactic can also be used to derive goals by showing
the absurdity of a hypothesis. *)
Theorem even5_nonsense :
ev 5 -> 2 + 2 = 9.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (ev_ev__ev) *)
(** Finding the appropriate thing to do induction on is a
bit tricky here: *)
Theorem ev_ev__ev : forall n m,
ev (n+m) -> ev n -> ev m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, optional (ev_plus_plus) *)
(** Here's an exercise that just requires applying existing lemmas. No
induction or even case analysis is needed, but some of the rewriting
may be tedious. *)
Theorem ev_plus_plus : forall n m p,
ev (n+m) -> ev (n+p) -> ev (m+p).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ####################################################### *)
(** * Discussion and Variations *)
(** ** Computational vs. Inductive Definitions *)
(** We have seen that the proposition "[n] is even" can be
phrased in two different ways -- indirectly, via a boolean testing
function [evenb], or directly, by inductively describing what
constitutes evidence for evenness. These two ways of defining
evenness are about equally easy to state and work with. Which we
choose is basically a question of taste.
However, for many other properties of interest, the direct
inductive definition is preferable, since writing a testing
function may be awkward or even impossible.
One such property is [beautiful]. This is a perfectly sensible
definition of a set of numbers, but we cannot translate its
definition directly into a Coq Fixpoint (or into a recursive
function in any other common programming language). We might be
able to find a clever way of testing this property using a
[Fixpoint] (indeed, it is not too hard to find one in this case),
but in general this could require arbitrarily deep thinking. In
fact, if the property we are interested in is uncomputable, then
we cannot define it as a [Fixpoint] no matter how hard we try,
because Coq requires that all [Fixpoint]s correspond to
terminating computations.
On the other hand, writing an inductive definition of what it
means to give evidence for the property [beautiful] is
straightforward. *)
(* ####################################################### *)
(** ** Parameterized Data Structures *)
(** So far, we have only looked at propositions about natural numbers. However,
we can define inductive predicates about any type of data. For example,
suppose we would like to characterize lists of _even_ length. We can
do that with the following definition. *)
Inductive ev_list {X:Type} : list X -> Prop :=
| el_nil : ev_list []
| el_cc : forall x y l, ev_list l -> ev_list (x :: y :: l).
(** Of course, this proposition is equivalent to just saying that the
length of the list is even. *)
Lemma ev_list__ev_length: forall X (l : list X), ev_list l -> ev (length l).
Proof.
intros X l H. induction H.
Case "el_nil". simpl. apply ev_0.
Case "el_cc". simpl. apply ev_SS. apply IHev_list.
Qed.
(** However, because evidence for [ev] contains less information than
evidence for [ev_list], the converse direction must be stated very
carefully. *)
Lemma ev_length__ev_list: forall X n, ev n -> forall (l : list X), n = length l -> ev_list l.
Proof.
intros X n H.
induction H.
Case "ev_0". intros l H. destruct l.
SCase "[]". apply el_nil.
SCase "x::l". inversion H.
Case "ev_SS". intros l H2. destruct l.
SCase "[]". inversion H2. destruct l.
SCase "[x]". inversion H2.
SCase "x :: x0 :: l". apply el_cc. apply IHev. inversion H2. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars (palindromes) *)
(** A palindrome is a sequence that reads the same backwards as
forwards.
- Define an inductive proposition [pal] on [list X] that
captures what it means to be a palindrome. (Hint: You'll need
three cases. Your definition should be based on the structure
of the list; just having a single constructor
c : forall l, l = rev l -> pal l
may seem obvious, but will not work very well.)
- Prove [pal_app_rev] that
forall l, pal (l ++ rev l).
- Prove [pal_rev] that
forall l, pal l -> l = rev l.
*)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(* Again, the converse direction is much more difficult, due to the
lack of evidence. *)
(** **** Exercise: 5 stars, optional (palindrome_converse) *)
(** Using your definition of [pal] from the previous exercise, prove
that
forall l, l = rev l -> pal l.
*)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(* ####################################################### *)
(** ** Relations *)
(** A proposition parameterized by a number (such as [ev] or
[beautiful]) can be thought of as a _property_ -- i.e., it defines
a subset of [nat], namely those numbers for which the proposition
is provable. In the same way, a two-argument proposition can be
thought of as a _relation_ -- i.e., it defines a set of pairs for
which the proposition is provable. *)
Module LeModule.
(** One useful example is the "less than or equal to"
relation on numbers. *)
(** The following definition should be fairly intuitive. It
says that there are two ways to give evidence that one number is
less than or equal to another: either observe that they are the
same number, or give evidence that the first is less than or equal
to the predecessor of the second. *)
Inductive le : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| le_n : forall n, le n n
| le_S : forall n m, (le n m) -> (le n (S m)).
Notation "m <= n" := (le m n).
(** Proofs of facts about [<=] using the constructors [le_n] and
[le_S] follow the same patterns as proofs about properties, like
[ev] in chapter [Prop]. We can [apply] the constructors to prove [<=]
goals (e.g., to show that [3<=3] or [3<=6]), and we can use
tactics like [inversion] to extract information from [<=]
hypotheses in the context (e.g., to prove that [(2 <= 1) -> 2+2=5].) *)
(** *** *)
(** Here are some sanity checks on the definition. (Notice that,
although these are the same kind of simple "unit tests" as we gave
for the testing functions we wrote in the first few lectures, we
must construct their proofs explicitly -- [simpl] and
[reflexivity] don't do the job, because the proofs aren't just a
matter of simplifying computations.) *)
Theorem test_le1 :
3 <= 3.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
apply le_n. Qed.
Theorem test_le2 :
3 <= 6.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
apply le_S. apply le_S. apply le_S. apply le_n. Qed.
Theorem test_le3 :
(2 <= 1) -> 2 + 2 = 5.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros H. inversion H. inversion H2. Qed.
(** *** *)
(** The "strictly less than" relation [n < m] can now be defined
in terms of [le]. *)
End LeModule.
Definition lt (n m:nat) := le (S n) m.
Notation "m < n" := (lt m n).
(** Here are a few more simple relations on numbers: *)
Inductive square_of : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
sq : forall n:nat, square_of n (n * n).
Inductive next_nat : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| nn : forall n:nat, next_nat n (S n).
Inductive next_even : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| ne_1 : forall n, ev (S n) -> next_even n (S n)
| ne_2 : forall n, ev (S (S n)) -> next_even n (S (S n)).
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars (total_relation) *)
(** Define an inductive binary relation [total_relation] that holds
between every pair of natural numbers. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars (empty_relation) *)
(** Define an inductive binary relation [empty_relation] (on numbers)
that never holds. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, optional (le_exercises) *)
(** Here are a number of facts about the [<=] and [<] relations that
we are going to need later in the course. The proofs make good
practice exercises. *)
Lemma le_trans : forall m n o, m <= n -> n <= o -> m <= o.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem O_le_n : forall n,
0 <= n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem n_le_m__Sn_le_Sm : forall n m,
n <= m -> S n <= S m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem Sn_le_Sm__n_le_m : forall n m,
S n <= S m -> n <= m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem le_plus_l : forall a b,
a <= a + b.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem plus_lt : forall n1 n2 m,
n1 + n2 < m ->
n1 < m /\ n2 < m.
Proof.
unfold lt.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem lt_S : forall n m,
n < m ->
n < S m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem ble_nat_true : forall n m,
ble_nat n m = true -> n <= m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem le_ble_nat : forall n m,
n <= m ->
ble_nat n m = true.
Proof.
(* Hint: This may be easiest to prove by induction on [m]. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem ble_nat_true_trans : forall n m o,
ble_nat n m = true -> ble_nat m o = true -> ble_nat n o = true.
Proof.
(* Hint: This theorem can be easily proved without using [induction]. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, optional (ble_nat_false) *)
Theorem ble_nat_false : forall n m,
ble_nat n m = false -> ~(n <= m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars (R_provability2) *)
Module R.
(** We can define three-place relations, four-place relations,
etc., in just the same way as binary relations. For example,
consider the following three-place relation on numbers: *)
Inductive R : nat -> nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| c1 : R 0 0 0
| c2 : forall m n o, R m n o -> R (S m) n (S o)
| c3 : forall m n o, R m n o -> R m (S n) (S o)
| c4 : forall m n o, R (S m) (S n) (S (S o)) -> R m n o
| c5 : forall m n o, R m n o -> R n m o.
(** - Which of the following propositions are provable?
- [R 1 1 2]
- [R 2 2 6]
- If we dropped constructor [c5] from the definition of [R],
would the set of provable propositions change? Briefly (1
sentence) explain your answer.
- If we dropped constructor [c4] from the definition of [R],
would the set of provable propositions change? Briefly (1
sentence) explain your answer.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
[]
*)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, optional (R_fact) *)
(** Relation [R] actually encodes a familiar function. State and prove two
theorems that formally connects the relation and the function.
That is, if [R m n o] is true, what can we say about [m],
[n], and [o], and vice versa?
*)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
End R.
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, advanced (subsequence) *)
(** A list is a _subsequence_ of another list if all of the elements
in the first list occur in the same order in the second list,
possibly with some extra elements in between. For example,
[1,2,3]
is a subsequence of each of the lists
[1,2,3]
[1,1,1,2,2,3]
[1,2,7,3]
[5,6,1,9,9,2,7,3,8]
but it is _not_ a subsequence of any of the lists
[1,2]
[1,3]
[5,6,2,1,7,3,8]
- Define an inductive proposition [subseq] on [list nat] that
captures what it means to be a subsequence. (Hint: You'll need
three cases.)
- Prove [subseq_refl] that subsequence is reflexive, that is,
any list is a subsequence of itself.
- Prove [subseq_app] that for any lists [l1], [l2], and [l3],
if [l1] is a subsequence of [l2], then [l1] is also a subsequence
of [l2 ++ l3].
- (Optional, harder) Prove [subseq_trans] that subsequence is
transitive -- that is, if [l1] is a subsequence of [l2] and [l2]
is a subsequence of [l3], then [l1] is a subsequence of [l3].
Hint: choose your induction carefully!
*)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, optional (R_provability) *)
(** Suppose we give Coq the following definition:
Inductive R : nat -> list nat -> Prop :=
| c1 : R 0 []
| c2 : forall n l, R n l -> R (S n) (n :: l)
| c3 : forall n l, R (S n) l -> R n l.
Which of the following propositions are provable?
- [R 2 [1,0]]
- [R 1 [1,2,1,0]]
- [R 6 [3,2,1,0]]
*)
(** [] *)
(* ##################################################### *)
(** * Programming with Propositions *)
(** As we have seen, a _proposition_ is a statement expressing a factual claim,
like "two plus two equals four." In Coq, propositions are written
as expressions of type [Prop]. . *)
Check (2 + 2 = 4).
(* ===> 2 + 2 = 4 : Prop *)
Check (ble_nat 3 2 = false).
(* ===> ble_nat 3 2 = false : Prop *)
Check (beautiful 8).
(* ===> beautiful 8 : Prop *)
(** *** *)
(** Both provable and unprovable claims are perfectly good
propositions. Simply _being_ a proposition is one thing; being
_provable_ is something else! *)
Check (2 + 2 = 5).
(* ===> 2 + 2 = 5 : Prop *)
Check (beautiful 4).
(* ===> beautiful 4 : Prop *)
(** Both [2 + 2 = 4] and [2 + 2 = 5] are legal expressions
of type [Prop]. *)
(** *** *)
(** We've mainly seen one place that propositions can appear in Coq: in
[Theorem] (and [Lemma] and [Example]) declarations. *)
Theorem plus_2_2_is_4 :
2 + 2 = 4.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** But they can be used in many other ways. For example, we have also seen that
we can give a name to a proposition using a [Definition], just as we have
given names to expressions of other sorts. *)
Definition plus_fact : Prop := 2 + 2 = 4.
Check plus_fact.
(* ===> plus_fact : Prop *)
(** We can later use this name in any situation where a proposition is
expected -- for example, as the claim in a [Theorem] declaration. *)
Theorem plus_fact_is_true :
plus_fact.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** *** *)
(** We've seen several ways of constructing propositions.
- We can define a new proposition primitively using [Inductive].
- Given two expressions [e1] and [e2] of the same type, we can
form the proposition [e1 = e2], which states that their
values are equal.
- We can combine propositions using implication and
quantification. *)
(** *** *)
(** We have also seen _parameterized propositions_, such as [even] and
[beautiful]. *)
Check (even 4).
(* ===> even 4 : Prop *)
Check (even 3).
(* ===> even 3 : Prop *)
Check even.
(* ===> even : nat -> Prop *)
(** *** *)
(** The type of [even], i.e., [nat->Prop], can be pronounced in
three equivalent ways: (1) "[even] is a _function_ from numbers to
propositions," (2) "[even] is a _family_ of propositions, indexed
by a number [n]," or (3) "[even] is a _property_ of numbers." *)
(** Propositions -- including parameterized propositions -- are
first-class citizens in Coq. For example, we can define functions
from numbers to propositions... *)
Definition between (n m o: nat) : Prop :=
andb (ble_nat n o) (ble_nat o m) = true.
(** ... and then partially apply them: *)
Definition teen : nat->Prop := between 13 19.
(** We can even pass propositions -- including parameterized
propositions -- as arguments to functions: *)
Definition true_for_zero (P:nat->Prop) : Prop :=
P 0.
(** *** *)
(** Here are two more examples of passing parameterized propositions
as arguments to a function.
The first function, [true_for_all_numbers], takes a proposition
[P] as argument and builds the proposition that [P] is true for
all natural numbers. *)
Definition true_for_all_numbers (P:nat->Prop) : Prop :=
forall n, P n.
(** The second, [preserved_by_S], takes [P] and builds the proposition
that, if [P] is true for some natural number [n'], then it is also
true by the successor of [n'] -- i.e. that [P] is _preserved by
successor_: *)
Definition preserved_by_S (P:nat->Prop) : Prop :=
forall n', P n' -> P (S n').
(** *** *)
(** Finally, we can put these ingredients together to define
a proposition stating that induction is valid for natural numbers: *)
Definition natural_number_induction_valid : Prop :=
forall (P:nat->Prop),
true_for_zero P ->
preserved_by_S P ->
true_for_all_numbers P.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars (combine_odd_even) *)
(** Complete the definition of the [combine_odd_even] function
below. It takes as arguments two properties of numbers [Podd] and
[Peven]. As its result, it should return a new property [P] such
that [P n] is equivalent to [Podd n] when [n] is odd, and
equivalent to [Peven n] otherwise. *)