-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
section_22.tex
387 lines (311 loc) · 37 KB
/
section_22.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% chapter.tex %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
%
% sample chapter
%
% Use this file as a template for your own input.
%
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% Springer-Verlag %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
%\motto{Use the template \emph{chapter.tex} to style the various elements of your chapter content.}
\subsection{The O-Minimality Bit (Parameterization)}
\sectionmark{Basics and Basic Cells}
\label{chap:om_bit} % Always give a unique label
% use \sectionmark{}
% to alter or adjust the chapter heading in the running head
%\sectionmark{Some Introductions}
We initially and have for a bit now been calling this section `the \om bit' to differentiate it from the number-theoretical part that is to come next. However, in the future, and as was alluded to a bit in the last section, this `\om bit' is about \param, and we shall generally go on to refer to this section and result as the `\param result,' or simply `\param.'
\bigskip
\centerline{\rule{0.3333\linewidth}{.2pt}}
\smallskip
\subsubsection{Setting}
In this section, we step back a bit from the specificity of $\R$ and work over a more general \om expansion of an ordered field, $\M = \Mltarithplus$. We let $I = (0, 1)$ the open unit interval, interpreted in our model, $\M$. For the next little while, we have Binyamini and Novikov \cite{binyamini_yomdingromov_2021} to thank for what is to come. We begin with some introduction to the world where we will find ourselves for the next little bit.
\begin{definition}
A \emph{\bc}, $\CIn[C]{n}$ is a set given by a product of copies of $I$ and singletons containing $0$, such that there are in total $n$ factors of this set product. On such a cell, $C$, a \cont map, $\funcdom{\phi}{C}{I^n}$ is called \emph{cellular} if
\begin{enumerate}
\item For $\phi = (\vonevm{\phi}{n})$ with each $\phi_j$ only dependent on the first $j$ coordinates.
\item For each $j$, and each $(\vonevm{x}{j - 1})$ in the projection of $C$ onto the the first $j - 1$ coordinates, the function $x_j \mapsto \phi_j(\vonevm{x}{j})$ is strictly increasing.
\end{enumerate}
\end{definition}
This next remark is one to remember, as it is a fact that we will be using and making references too often.
\begin{remark}
Suppose $\funcdom{\phi}{C}{I^n}$, $\funcdom{\psi}{\pri{C}}{C}$ are both cellular. Then so too is their composition, $\funcdom{\phi \circ \psi}{\pri{C}}{I^n}$.
\end{remark}
Checking that the two necessary conditions hold is rather trivial here and not included. This next bit is mostly just notational.
\begin{definition}[and notation for the norm]
Given $\XRn[U]{n}$ and $\funcdom{f}{U}{\R^m}$ a $C^r$ map, we set the $r$-norm of $f$ to be
\begin{align*}
\rnorm[r]{\ f \ } = \left( \max_{\abs{\alpha} \leq r}{ \sup{ \abs{ \ ( D^{(\alpha)} f_j(x) \ } } } \right) \cdot \cfrac{1}{\alpha !}
\end{align*}
\end{definition}
Note that the scaling by factorial $\alpha$ is not strictly relevant but more of a convenience. Ultimately, just so it is entirely clear what the point of all this is, what we are aiming to find here is parameterizations into the cellular maps on which these norms are bounded. To that end, consider:
\begin{definition}
Let $r \in \N$ and $\CIn[x]{n}$ definable. Then a \emph{\cellrparam} (CRP) is a finite set, $\Phi$, of \defnb $C^r$ \cellr maps such that each
\begin{align*}
\rnorm[r]{\phi} \leq 1
\end{align*}
for each $\phi \in \Phi$, and that the union of their images covers $X$ -- that is,
\begin{align*}
\bigcup_{\phi \in \Phi} \image{\phi} = X.
\end{align*}
\end{definition}
Suppose now we want a \cellrparam between definable sets -- what does that require?
\begin{definition}
Suppose we have some $\CIn[Y]{m}$, and $\funcdom{f}{X}{Y}$ \defnb. Then. \cellrparam[r] of $f$ is a \cellrparam[r] $\Phi$ of $X$, with the \emph{extra} property that
\begin{align*}
\rnorm[r]{f \circ \phi} \leq 1
\end{align*}
for all $\phi$ in $\Phi$.
\end{definition}
\subsubsection{Do These Even Exist?}
As is often amusing to those outside of mathematics, and even those \emph{in} maths (at least from the perspective of a graduate student in the area), so often we find ourselves setting up a series of definitions and such defining objects that we wish to study -- with a capstone theorem being that they exist at all. While this may seem the completely backwards way to go about doing things, it is often one that ends up working quite well -- but not always. We're sure, of course, that we don't need to recite the (likely apocryphal) story of the aspiring mathematician who worked for quite a while in this way on H\"older continuous maps with $\alpha > 1$ -- having only before seen the case with $\alpha$ in the unit interval. It was only at his defence that he was asked to show an example of such a \emph{non-constant} map -- which, of course, does not exist. Of course, similar apocrypha exist about anti-metric spaces and other seemingly fun ideas that end off in nothing of much use. Luckily, or perhaps even more accurately, \emph{skillfully} and intuitively from our definitions, it turns out that our setup \emph{does} end up working out for us as desired. We now go on to state and prove the theorem that these objects we have described above do, in fact, exist and are non-trivial.
\subsubsection{Yes -- And Here's a Proof}
Just like with the proof of $\CD$, we are going to have two inductive towers, where we again employ the back-and-forth method to prove the theorem for all $n$. Note as another similarity that the first statement is one about sets and the second of functions.
\begin{theorem}[Parameterization (by Binyamini \& Novikov)]
%Let $n \in \N$. Just like with the proof of $\CD$, we are going to have two inductive towers that we wish to prove to get the theorem for all $n$. Unlike \textbf{that} proof, however, we don't employ the back-and-forth method we used there, as that will prove unnecessary here. Similarly, though, we see that the first statement is about sets and the second of functions. The two statements in our theorem are
Let $n \in \N$. Then
\begin{enumerate}[label={}]
\item[$\In$ ] If $r \in \N$ and $\CIn[X]{n}$ is \defnb, then $X$ has a \cellrparam.
\item[$\IIn$ ] If $r, \ m \in \N$ and $\CIn[X]{n}$, $\CIn[Y]{m}$, and $\funcdom{f}{X}{Y}$ \defnb, then $f$ has a \cellrparam.
\end{enumerate}
Of course, it is clear that $\IIn$ is the more difficult of the two to prove, and in fact, $\IIn$ can then be used to prove $\In$ (so we have perhaps presented them in a bit of a disordered way, in absence of the reflection with the \CD theorem).
\label{thm:existence}
\end{theorem}
Before we start the proof, we give provide a quick remark on these \cellrparams, and that is that we can \emph{almost} compose these \cellrparams. This is to say essentially the following:
\begin{remark}
Suppose $\Phi$ is a \cellrparam of some $\CIn[X]{m}$ and that for each $\phi \in \Phi$, given $\funcdom{\phi}{C}{X}$, we have a \cellrparam $\Psi_{\phi}$ of $C$. What we then would like to do is take all the $\phi$ and compose with all corresponding $\Psi_{\phi}$, and receive cellular maps. We \emph{almost} get this result. For example, taking some $\psi \in \Psi_{\phi}$, We can compute to show
\begin{align*}
\rnorm[r]{\phi \circ \psi} \leq c_{n, \ r},
\end{align*}
which, although not necessarily 1, is finite and so bounded. Of course, we can \emph{make} this constant to be $1$ by doing a bit of extra parameterization. Start by covering $\pri{C} = \dom{\psi}$ with $(c + 1)^k$ boxes, where we take $k = \dim{\psi}$, we let $c \coloneqq c_{n, \ r}$, and each box is itself a translate of $(0, \sfrac{1}{c})^k$. This is justified due to the fact that on each such box, we have a natural linear map from $(0, 1)^k$ to $(0, \sfrac{1}{c})^k$ -- and in so applying these natural maps, we end up with $c_{n, \ r} = 1$ after the computation, for each $\phi$ and $\psi$. So now, at the expense of ending up with a whole bunch more maps, we end up with a \cellrparam. What we just described -- the process of going from a constant of $n$ and $r$ to 1 using linear maps will hence be referred to as \textbf{linear substitution}. Going on, and in the next proof, we are going to be justifying parts \emph{by linear substitution} quite a bit, so what may have seemed like a brief detour is actually quite important
\end{remark}
\begin{remark}
This may seem completely apropos of nothing, but now and for the rest of these notes, we assume our model, $\M$, to be $\aleph_0$-saturated. If this idea is familiar to you: great. Otherwise, don't worry too much about it. Consider the idea of saturation as somewhat analogous to compactness in a sense; where the specified saturation determines the basis for a particular topological construction. Essentially this assumption allows us just a bit more stringency to get our result more cleanly than we may otherwise. If you want a little more explanation, refer to the snazzy little box below (or up on the top of the next page, as it may be).
\end{remark}
\pagebreak
\begin{svgraybox}
\textbf{For those a little more interested} \\
In essence, $\M$ being $\omega$-saturated for $\omega$ a cardinal means that for $A \subseteq M$ with cardinality less than $\omega$, the $A$-\defnb subsets of $M^n$ form a basis for a topology (called the $A$-topology) on $M^n$ which is compact Hausdorff, and for which $A$-\defnb sets are the open and closed sets. We take $\aleph_0$-saturation (allowing only finite, not even countable $A$ sets), but this allows us to use definable selection to get a uniform version of a proposition we need in our proof. Further, but not relevant here, $\aleph_0$-saturated models can be elementarily extended to $\aleph_1$-saturated models, where work can be done that may not be possible in the original model -- but can then be applied back due to being an elementary extension. Saturation is actually quite important if one is to discuss this topic in more generality and without making some of the assumptions we do, but for our purposes, this is a \textit{sweep-under-the-rug} kind of idea.
\end{svgraybox}
Not to keep the eager reader too antsy about getting to the proof of the above theorem, but we are first going to start with a lemma (and then another -- which some may even say is starting with two \lemmas) that will make the proof of $\IIn$ \emph{quite} a bit nicer for ourselves.
\subsubsection{A Few \Lemmas to Get us Going}
\sectionmark{Some Useful Results}
\begin{lemma}
Let $n, r \in \N$, and suppose that every $\funcdom{F}{\pri{X}}{I}$ \defnb on a \defnb $\pri{X}$ of dimension $n$ has a \cellrparam. Then for every definable $\funcdom{G}{X}{I^m}$ with $m \in \N$ and such that $\dim{X} = n$ has a \cellrparam.
\label{lem:crp-pt2}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}[of Lemma \ref{lem:crp-pt2}]
Fix some $G = (\vonevm{G}{m})$ and let $\Phi_1$ be a \cellrparam of $G_1$ (which we know we can find by assumption). It is then enough to find a \cellrparam of $G \circ \phi$ for $\phi \in \Phi_1$, and then use \emph{linear substitution} as described it before. So, we can suppose $\rnorm{G_1} \leq 1$. Recall of course that by our assumption, $G_1$ depended only on its first indeterminate -- and so we can similarly get a \cellrparam, $\Phi_2$ of $G_2$. Taking some $\phi \in \Phi_2$ then evidently (as before) $G_2 \circ \phi$ is as desired -- but now we need to worry about $G_1 \circ \phi$. Generically, we get that $\rnorm{G_1 \circ \phi} \leq c_{r, \ n}$. We can then keep doing this for all $3 \leq j \leq m$, and then for each have that $\rnorm{G_j} \leq c_{r, \ n}$. At this point, we can do a whole bunch of our linear substitutions to get a bound of $1$ for each $j$.
\end{proof}
\begin{remark}
It may not be immediately obvious why the above lemma is useful to us. Principally, its use will be in proving $\IIn$ in the theorem, where it essentially says that we get to treat our $\funcdom{f}{X}{Y}$ for $\CIn[Y]{n}$ equivalently to some $\funcdom{\hat{f}}{X}{\hat{Y}}$ for $\hat{Y} \subseteq I$ -- essentially preventing us from having to have to deal with vectorial image, and only consider the case of one variable in the codomain. This is quite nice indeed.
\end{remark}
\begin{proof}[of Theorem \ref{thm:existence}]
It should be clear that we induct on $n$ to prove this. The statement $\In[1]$ is immediately obvious from what we've said earlier, so we need to prove $\IIn[1]$ to finish the base case. Unfortunately, this is nowhere near as immediate -- so much so that we appeal to a lemma.
\begin{lemma}[Gromov]
Suppose $r \geq 2$, $\funcdom{f}{I}{I}$ \defnb and $C^{r-1}$ with $\rnorm[r-1]{f} \leq 1$. Then $f$ has a \cellrparam.
\label{lem:gromov_r2}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}[of Lemma \ref{lem:gromov_r2}]
First, by applying the \SMt, we can break up into intervals on each of which we assume that our $f$ is $r$-times differentiable -- and further that its $r$-th derivative is strictly monotonic (if the derivative is 0, then there's nothing further needed). Without loss of generality, we assume one of these intervals is $I$ itself. We take $f^{(r)}$ strictly decreasing on $I$, and $f^{(r)} > 0$. Then, by applying the mean value theorem (which we took for granted as part of the clarity of implementing calculus-type concepts in our model), for all $x \in I$ there is some $\xi_n \in (0, x)$ such that
\begin{align*}
\cfrac{c_r}{x} &\geq \cfrac{f^{(r-1)}(x) - f^{(r-1)}(0)}{x} & = f^{(r)}(\xi_n) \\
& &\geq f^{(r)}(x)
\end{align*}
for $c_r$ some constant depending on $r$. Let $\funcdef{g}{x}{f(x^2)}$. Then we already have that $\rnorm[r-1]{g}$ is bounded, and so it suffices to check for $r$. Computing this, we get
\begin{align*}
g^{(r)}(x) = a + c_r \cdot f^{(r)}(x^2) \cdot x^r,
\end{align*}
for $a$ simply the sum of some bounded terms (about which needn't worry). But, by the above,
\begin{align*}
f^{(r)}(x^2) \cdot x^r \leq c_r \cdot x^{r - 2}
\end{align*}
and since $r$ was presumed to be at least $2$, then this is bounded as desired. So, we get that $\rnorm{g} < c_r$, which we can again make 1 by linear substitution.
\end{proof}
Gromov's lemma gave us the case where $r$ was at least 2, so now we handle the case where $r$ is 1.
\begin{lemma}
Suppose $\funcdom{f}{I}{I}$ is a \defnb function, and $r \in \N$. Then there exist \defnb $C^r$ functions, $\vonevm{\phi}{k}$ with each given $\funcdom{\phi_j}{I}{I^2}$, whose images cover $\graph{f}$ such that that $\rnorm{\phi_j} \leq 1$, and each coordinate of each $\phi_j$ is either constant or strictly monotonic.
\label{lem:existence_r1}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}[of Lemma \ref{lem:existence_r1}]
By \sm, we can assume that $f$ is $C^1$ on $I$ and either constant or strictly monotonic with derivative $\pri{f}$ sitting in one of the following intervals over $I$:
\begin{itemize}
\item $(\ - \infty, \ 1 \ )$
\item $[\ -1, \ 0 \ )$
\item $( \ 0, \ 1 \ ]$
\item $( \ 1, \ \infty \ )$.
\end{itemize}
We can then assume that $0 < \pri{f} \leq 1$ by using $\inv{f}$ in place of $f$ if necessary, or reversing the orientation of $I$ (depending on which of the follow above intervals $\pri{f}$ sits in). Then, we simply apply the previous lemma $r - 1$ times. to get a parameterization, $\Phi$ of $I$ such that $\rnorm{f \circ \phi} \leq 1$, and so we take $\left\{ \ (\phi, \ f \circ \phi) \ \colon \ \phi \in \Phi \ \right\}$ as our parameterization of the graph.
\end{proof}
So, we've now proved (through the previous two \lemmas) the parameterization of the graph of $f$, and what we want to prove now is the existence of a \cellrparam. We are now equipped to do so (recall that we are currently proving $\IIn[1]$). It suffices to do this for a \defnb $\funcdom{f}{I}{I}$. We apply the previous lemma to get a parameterization, $\Phi$ of the graph of $f$. We address each $\phi$ in the parameterization; if $\phi \in \Phi$ has strictly decreasing first coordinate, we compose with $1 - x$ (making it increasing), and otherwise leave it be; so when we take the set
\begin{align*}
\left\{ \ \phi_1 \ \colon \ \phi = (\phi_1, \ \phi_2) \in \Phi \right\}
\end{align*}
we are ensured that it is a \cellrparam of $I$. Now all we need to check is composition with $f$ holding as expected. Recall that $\rnorm{f \circ \phi_1} = \rnorm{\phi_2} \leq 1$, and so we do have a \cellrparam of $f$.
That may have felt like quite a lot, especially for just the base case, and so again, we introduce our old friend, the horizontal line, in hopes that it brings us a respite in what may be an overwhelming time. If not at all distressed, feel free to ignore it entirely.
\centerline{\rule{0.6667\linewidth}{.2pt}}
\smallskip
Now isn't that \emph{pleasant}? Try not to spend too long, and we will now move on to the inductive stage of this proof.
We assume that $\In[m]$ and $\IIn[m]$ hold for $m \leq n$. We start by proving the (much) easier of the two parts, $\In[n+1]$. By \cd, we can suppose $\CIn[X]{n+1}$ is a cell, and so either the graph of a function or the space between two functions.
If the former, that is, $X = \graph{f}$ for $\funcdom{f}{\pri{X}}{I}$ a \cont \defnb function on some $\CIn[\pri{X}]{n}$, then applying $\IIn[n]$ to this function, we get a \cellrparam of $f$, $\Phi$ -- and so taking some $\phi \in \Phi$, we have that $\funcdom{\phi}{\pri{C}}{I^n}$ for $\pri{C}$ some basic cell in $I^n$. Simply set $C = \pri{C} \times \{ \ 0 \ \}$ and define
\begin{align*}
\psi &\colon C \to I^{n + 1} \\
\psi &\colon (x, 0) \mapsto (\phi(x), \ f \circ \phi(x)).
\end{align*}
Since $\rnorm{f \circ \phi} \leq 1$, taking all such $\psi$ gives a \cellrparam of $X$ as desired.
Supposing now instead that $X = (f, \ g)_{\pri{X}}$ is the space between two graphs, we apply $\IIn[n]$ to the map $(f, \ g)$ (note the perhaps confusing notation; the non-subscripted $(f, g)$ is a \emph{map}, and not the space between graphs) we get a \cellrparam, $\Phi$ of $(f, \ g)$. Again, taking some $\phi \in \Phi$ we have that $\funcdom{\phi}{\pri{C}}{I^n}$ for $\pri{C} \subseteq I^n$ a basic cell. Similarly to the last case (and in analogue to our definition of cells), set $C = \pri{C} \times I$ and define
\begin{align*}
\psi &\colon C \to I^{n + 1} \\
\psi &\colon (\pri{x}, x_{n+1}) \mapsto (\phi(\pri{x}), \ g \circ \phi(\pri{x}) \cdot x_{n + 1} + (1 - x_{n+1}) \cdot f \circ \phi(\pri{x}) ).
\end{align*}
Since we have already that $\rnorm{g \circ \phi} \leq 1$ and $\rnorm{f \circ \phi} \leq 1$, we easily see that $\rnorm{\psi} \leq c$, which can be changed to a bound of 1 by linear substitution. Thus again, we get a \cellrparam of $X$ -- and now, we have proven $\In[n+1]$ with all cases exhausted. We hate to remind the reader that this was the easy one, and not just by a little bit. Just because this author contends that we all deserve it, \emph{please} once, and perhaps finally, enjoy the following line.
\centerline{\rule{0.6667\linewidth}{.2pt}}
\smallskip
We assume $\In[m]$ for $m \leq n$, and $\IIn[m]$ for $m < n$, and show that $\IIn[n]$ holds to start the induction. But first, we need that uniform version of $\IIn[n-1]$ that we alluded to earlier (should you have read the very snazzy box).
\subsubsection{A Uniform Version of One of Our Statements}
\sectionmark{Doing the Induction}
%\begin{svgraybox}
% The following was presented as an exercise to the viewer, but we will present it as a proposition in these notes, following our own (hopefully correct) proof.
%\end{svgraybox}
As it turns out, it will be necessary (in the way we prove the next bit) to use a \emph{uniform} version of $\IIn[n-1]$, which we will present as a proposition. This is where the importance of our model being $\aleph_0$-saturated comes into play, and one uses this, along with \defnb choice, to prove that the uniform result follows from the non-uniform. We do not include a detailed proof here, but for details on this, the reader is directed to \cite{bhardwaj_pilawilkie_2022}, where this is addressed in Corollaries 7.1 and 7.2. For particularities, the latter portion of Appendix B can be referenced.
\begin{proposition}[Uniform Version of $(\textrm{II})_{n-1}$]
Supposing $\IIn[n-1]$ holds, and that $\funcdom{f}{I \times I^{n - 1}}{I}$ is \defnb, there is a partition, $\vonevm{I}{k}$ of $I$ into \defnb sets such that for each $j = 1, \hdots, k$, there is a uniform parameterization of $f$, ($\Phi_j$ a set of \defnb maps given $\funcdom{\phi}{I_j \times C}{I^{n-1}}$ for $C$ a basic cell in $I^{n - 1}$ depending on $\phi$) such that if $a \in I_j$, then $\Phi_{j, \ a} = \left\{ \ \phi(a, \ \hdots) \ \colon \ \phi \in \Phi_j \ \right\}$ is a \cellrparam of $f(a, \ \hdots)$.
\label{prop:uniform_param_exc}
\end{proposition}
\subsubsection{Finally Inducting}
We are now ready to prove $\IIn[n]$ with that under our belt. We do this by a series of reductions that will make a seemingly more difficult result much more within reach. First, suppose $\funcdom{f}{X}{I}$, with $\CIn[X]{n}$ \defnb. What we want then is a \cellrparam for $f$. By $\In[n]$, we can reparameterize $X$ and work with each chart separately. As such, we can assume that $X$ is a basic cell. If this has any 0 coordinates, we can use $\IIn[m]$ for some $m < n$, and we are done. So, we assume that all coordinates of $X$ are non-zero. This, of course, then means that, because it is a basic cell, it \emph{must} be $I^n$ itself. So, we are now considering the function $\funcdom{f}{I^n}{I}$. This is our first reduction. Our next reduction is going to be showing that we can assume $f$ to be $C^r$ and for each $a$ in our interval, evaluating with $a$ as our first coordinate gives a map (on $I^{n-1}$) with bounded derivative (that is, $\rnorm{f(a, \ \hdots)} \leq 1$).
This is where the \emph{uniform} version of $\IIn[n-1]$ becomes useful. We apply the proposition to $\funcdom{f}{I \times I^{n-1}}{I}$ What the \emph{uniform} version told us was that we get \emph{finitely-many} of these parameterizing families, $\Phi_j$ as above, and a partition $(\vonevm{I}{k})$. Going even one level deeper, for each such $I_j$, we can reparameterize (as we did earlier) to assume that each $I_j$ is just $I$. Thus, partitioning and rescaling, we can take each $I_j = I$ (after which point we now drop the $j$ from the notation). We then fix some $\funcdom{\phi}{I \times C}{I^{n-1}}$ for $C = I^{n - 1}$. Notice we ignore the immediately solvable case (as before) where would could just appeal to one of the assumed statements for $\IIn[m]$, $m < n$ in our strong induction. Setting now
\begin{align*}
G(\vonevm{x}{n}) = f(x_1, \phi(\vonevm{x}{n}))
\end{align*}
by the parameterization from (a good bit) earlier, we get that for each $a \in I$, we have that $\rnorm{G(a, \ \hdots)} \leq 1$. By \scd, there is a \defnb $\CIn[Z]{n}$ having dimension less than $n$, and such that the function restriction $G \ \vert_{I^n \setminus Z}$ is $C^r$. Using $\In[m]$ for $m < n$, we find a \cellrparam, $\Phi_Z$ for $Z$ (which we must be able to since $Z$ has dimension less than $n$). Since $\dim{Z} < n$, if $\phi \in \Phi_Z$ has domain $C$ and $C$ has a 0 coordinate, then we can apply $\IIn[n-1]$ to each $G \circ \phi$, for each $\phi$. To summarize, in particular because it is easy to get lost in this, what we have done is reparameterize $f$ on $Z$ -- and now we go on to worry about the complement of $Z$ in $I^n$.
That is all to say, we are left again with the restricted function $G \ \vert_{I^n \setminus Z}$ -- which the keen amongst you should notice (the restriction of) is a set in $\In[n]$. Even for the less keen, we know from $\In[n]$ that we can parameterize such sets -- and so the end is (perhaps) within sight! Suppose we have a \cellrparam, $\Psi$ of $I^n \setminus Z$. Fixing some $\psi \in \Psi$, we can define
\begin{align*}
t &\colon C \to I^n \setminus Z,
\end{align*}
and we presume that $C$ is \emph{not} $I^n$ for reasons of non-triviality.
We know that, by definition, $\psi$ maps into the space where $G$ is $C^r$, and so $\comp{G}{\psi}$ is $C^r$. For $\alpha \in (\N)^{n-1}$ a multi-index, with order $\abs{\alpha} \leq r$, for any $a \in I$, we have to check that, being cellular (and so depending only on the first-coordinate, $a$),
\begin{align*}
\abs{D^{\alpha} \ (\comp{G}{\psi})(a, \ \hdots)} &= \abs{D^{\alpha} \left( \comp{(G(\psi_1(a), \ \hdots)}{(\vmvn{\psi}{2}{n})} \right)}
\end{align*}
since $\psi$ is cellular. And so, we can conclude that
\begin{align*}
\abs{D^{\alpha} \left( \comp{(G(\psi_1(a), \ \hdots)}{(\vmvn{\psi}{2}{n})} \right)} \leq c_{n, \ r}
\end{align*}
since $\rnorm{G(b, \ \hdots)} \leq 1$ for each $b \in Z$ (in particular where $b = \phi_1(a)$) and $\rnorm{\psi} \leq 1$ -- and so as ever, by linear substitution, we can make our $c_{n, \ r}$ equal to 1.
So, we can assume that $\rnorm{\comp{G}{\psi}(a, \ \hdots)} \leq 1$ for each $a \in I$. We are now so close to \emph{almost} done.
So, should we replace $f$ with $\comp{G}{\psi}$ for $\phi_1$, we may then assume that $\funcdom{f}{I^n}{I}$ is $C^r$, and that for each $a \in I^{n - 1}$, we have $\rnorm{f(a, \ \hdots)} \leq 1$.
\subsubsection{A Final Lemma (For This Proof)}
We now need one quick lemma to finish off (though we will not be proving it until a bit later).
\begin{lemma}
Suppose $\funcdom{f}{I^n}{I}$ is \defnb, and $C^1$, and suppose as well that
\begin{align*}
\left\vert \ \cfrac{\partial f}{\partial x_j}(x) \ \right\vert \leq 1
\end{align*}
for each $x \in I^n$, and $j = 2, \ \hdots, n$. Then, the set of $a \in I$ such that $\cfrac{\partial f}{\partial x_1}(a, \ \hdots)$ is unbounded is finite
\label{lem:fin_a_unbounded}
\end{lemma}
The proof of this lemma is to come later, and for now, we will take this fact for granted.
%\begin{proof}[of Lemma \ref{lem:fin_a_unbounded}]
%\end{proof}
Recalling where we were in our proof, we can take $\N^n$ and order it first by degree and then lexicographically. We take then that $\alpha \in \N^n$ is at least in this ordering such that
\begin{align*}
\left\vert D^{\alpha}(f) \right\vert > 1
\end{align*}
-- that is, its derivatives are `big.' If there is no such $\alpha$, we are finished! Otherwise, we parameterize $f$ to bound \emph{this} derivative, and such that the resulting (next) function has increased $\alpha$, and continue this inductively. We now show that this is, in fact, something we \emph{can} do -- that is, ensure that we increase $\alpha$ -- and then finish by induction.
First note that our multi-index, $\alpha$, living in $\N^n$ must have $\alpha_1 \geq 1$. By the above (unproven) lemma, there are only finitely-many $a \in I$ such that $D^{\alpha} f(a, \ \hdots)$ is unbounded. As such, we can use $\IIn[n-1]$ to handle these cases, and so assume that for each $a \in I$, we do have $D^{\alpha} f(a, \ \hdots)$ bounded.
Now, we define
\begin{align*}
S = \left\{ \ x \in \I^n \ \colon \left\vert D^{\alpha} f(x) \right\vert \geq \cfrac{1}{2} \sup_{\pri{x} \in I} \left( D^{\alpha} f(x, \pri{x}) \right) \ \right\}.
\end{align*}
By our assumption, we know this supremum to be bounded, and so this set is actually definable (not in the \om sense, just in that it makes sense to define). By \defnb (this time in the \om sense) choice, there is a \defnb $\funcdom{\gamma}{I}{S}$ with $\gamma_1(t) = t$ simply the identity. Consider the map
\begin{align*}
t \mapsto (\gamma(t), \ D^{\pri{\alpha}} f (\gamma(t)))
\end{align*}
where $\pri{\alpha} = (\alpha_1 - 1, \alpha_2, \ \hdots, \ \alpha_n)$. By $\IIn[1]$, we get a \cellrparam, $\Phi$, of this map. Take some $\phi \in \Phi$, and consider
\begin{align*}
G(x_1, \ \hdots, \ x_n) = f(\phi(x_1), \ x_2, \ \hdots, \ x_n ).
\end{align*}
This makes sense because, as part of a \cellrparam of a map on the unit interval, $\phi$ maps into the unit interval itself.
\begin{svgraybox}
A pithy little aside that is just \emph{too} good not to mention here is Dr Jones' comment about how ``one should never differentiate in public'' -- which we find quite amusing.
\end{svgraybox}
Computing for $\beta < \alpha$, we get
\begin{align*}
\left\vert \ D^{\beta} \ G \ \right\vert < \cnr
\end{align*}
for $c_{n, \ r}$ a constant depending on $n$ and $r$ as usual -- so this is fine. What we need to worry about is $\alpha$. When we consider $D^{\alpha} \ G$, we are differentiating $f$ to some order \emph{other} than specified by $\alpha$ (but smaller, which is okay), but we may run into problem cases where we take the $\alpha$ derivative of $f$, and then a bunch of $\phi$s come out. So, computing $D^{\alpha} \ G$, we get some number of terms dependent on $n$ and $r$, and bounded by $\cnr$ plus some term
\begin{align*}
\pri{\phi}(x_1)^{\alpha_1} \ \cdot \ \left( D^{\alpha} f \right) \ (\phi_1(x_1), \ x_2, \ \hdots, \ x_n)
\end{align*}
with the left-most term coming from taking the derivative of the expression above in $\phi$. By our definition of $S$ and $\gamma$, we have that
\begin{align*}
\left\vert \ \pri{\phi}(x_1)^{\alpha_1} \ \cdot \ (D^{\alpha} f) \ (\phi(x_1), \ x_2, \ \cdots, x_n) \ \right\vert &\leq 2 \cdot \left\vert \ \pri{\phi}(x_1) \ \right\vert^{\alpha_1} \ \cdot \left\vert \ (D^{\alpha} f) \ (\gamma(\phi(x_1))) \ \right\vert \\
&\leq 2 \cdot \left\vert \ \pri{\phi}(x_1) \ \right\vert \ \cdot \left\vert \ (D^{\alpha} f) \ (\gamma(\phi(x_1))) \ \right\vert
\end{align*}
since $\alpha_1 \geq 1$, and $\card{\pri{\phi}} \leq 1$. Thus, we need to bound this right-hand side of the inequality. To do so, we compute
\begin{align}
\cfrac{\partial}{\partial x_1} \left( \left( D^{\pri{\alpha}} f \right) \left( \gamma (\phi(x_1)) \right) \right) &= \pri{\phi}(x_1) \cdot \left( D^{\alpha} f \right) \left( \gamma (\phi(x_1)) \right) \label{eqn:param_deriv_1} \\
&\quad \quad+ \pri{\phi}(x_1) \cdot \sum_{j=2}^{n} \cfrac{\partial \gamma_j}{\partial t} \ (\phi(x_1)) \ \cdot \ \left( D^{{\alpha}^{(j)}} f \right) \ \left( \gamma(\phi(t)) \right)
\label{eqn:param_deriv_2}
\end{align}
note that we ignore the $\pri{\gamma_1}$ since it is just the identity map. We have that $a^{(j)} = \pri{\alpha} + (0, \ \hdots, \ 0, \ 1, \ 0, \ \hdots, \ 0)$ with $1$ at the $j$-th coordinate. We claim that this is sufficient to control (prove the bound) as claimed.
Recall that $\Phi$ is a \cellrparam of the map taking $t$ to $(\gamma(t), \ D^{\pri{\alpha}} f(\gamma(t)))$, so substituting in our various $\phi$, we get bounded derivatives. That is, the left-hand side of Equation \ref{eqn:param_deriv_1} is bounded by $\Phi$, a \cellrparam of $\left( D^{\pri{\alpha}} f \right)(\gamma(t))$. Similarly, we have that each partial derivative in the sum in Equation \ref{eqn:param_deriv_2} is also bounded, again by $\Phi$, a \cellrparam of $\gamma$ -- and the other incidence of $\pri{\phi}(x_1)$ in Equation \ref{eqn:param_deriv_2} is bounded for the same reason. The final factor in Equation \ref{eqn:param_deriv_2} is finally also bounded because $\alpha^{(j)} < \alpha$, and $\alpha$ was assumed to be minimal such that the derivative exceeded $1$. Hence, putting this all together, we get that the right-hand side of Equation \ref{eqn:param_deriv_1} \emph{must be bounded}; to be clear, that is
\begin{align*}
\pri{\phi}(x_1) \cdot \left( D^{\alpha} f \right) \left( \gamma (\phi(x_1)) \right)
\end{align*}
is bounded.
Now what to do with all this? Well, we have that (skipping right past the linear substitution step), that
\begin{align*}
\lvrv{ \pri{\phi}(x_1) \cdot \left( D^{\alpha} f \right) \left( \gamma (\phi(x_1)) \right) } \leq 1,
\end{align*}
and finally we are finished with the proof.
\end{proof}
\sectionmark{Nearly There Now}
That is, of course, just a very funny joke we cruelly taunt the reader with -- as if you'll remember correctly, we never actually went on to prove that last lemma, whose proof we left for some poor sob down the road. It's perhaps just unfortunate then that that poor sob is, in fact, ourselves. However, before we prove that lemma directly, we first prove another lemma in what is becoming an increasingly ridiculous chain of \lemmas, each feeding into one other, almost and perhaps with no end in sight. But that's mathematics for you.
\begin{lemma}
Suppose $\funcdom{f}{M \times I}{I}$ a family of functions mapping from the unit interval into itself a \defnb family of $C^1$ functions. Then, there is a $c > 0$ such that for any $a \in M$, and $B > 0$, the set
\begin{align*}
T = \left\{ \ t \in I \ \colon \ \lvrv{ \pri{f_a}(t) > B } \ \right\}
\end{align*}
has $\mu(T) < \cfrac{c}{B} \ $, for $\mu$ the sum of lengths of intervals function.
\label{lem:small_lemma_in_support}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}[of Lemma \ref{lem:small_lemma_in_support}]
Consider the two sets whose union compose that in the original statement,
\begin{align*}
T_{+} &= \left\{ \ t \in I \ \colon \ \pri{f_a}(t) > B \ \right\} \\
T_{-} &= \left\{ \ t \in I \ \colon \ \pri{f_a}(t) < -B \ \right\}.
\end{align*}
These are both given by finite unions of open intervals, and that number of intervals, by \om, is bounded uniformly in $a$ and $B$. So, each of these intervals has length not exceeding $\frac{1}{B}$ given we have that $\funcdom{f_a}{I}{I}$ (by mean value theorem as before). Of course, then, the result almost immediately follows because we may take our constant to be the number of intervals in these two sets.
\end{proof}
We \emph{now} use this last lemma to prove the lemma we took for granted during the more arduous proof of parameterization. Because it's been a bit, we recall the theorem (mostly in full) before providing a proof.
\begin{lemma}[Really Lemma \ref{lem:fin_a_unbounded}]
Suppose $\funcdom{f}{I^n}{I}$ is \defnb, and $C^1$, and suppose as well that
\begin{align*}
\lvrv{ \cfrac{\partial f}{\partial x_j}(x) } \leq 1
\end{align*}
for each $x \in I^n$, and $j = 2, \ \hdots, n$. Then, the set of $a \in I$ such that $\cfrac{\partial f}{\partial x_1}(a, \ \hdots)$ is unbounded is finite
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}[of Lemma \ref{lem:fin_a_unbounded}]
Supposing otherwise, the this set must contain an interval, and we can assume that interval to be $I$ -- that is,
\begin{align*}
\pderiv[f]{x_1} (a, \ \hdots)
\end{align*}
is unbounded for all $a \in I$. By choice and \sm, we can assume that we get a $C^1$ $\funcdom{\gamma}{(0, \ \infty) \times I}{I^{n - 1}}$ such that for all $B > 0$ and $t \in I$, we have
\begin{align*}
\lvrv{ \pderiv[f]{x_j} (t, \gamma_B(t)) } > B,
\end{align*}
and is \defnb. Applying the previous lemma (Lemma \ref{lem:small_lemma_in_support}) to the coordinates of $\gamma_B$ and to the family $f(t, \ \gamma_B(t))$, there is a constant, $C$, such that outside a set of measure $\leq \frac{C}{B}$, we have
\begin{align*}
\lvrv{ \deriv{t} f(t, \gamma_{B}(t)) } \leq \cfrac{B}{3}
\end{align*}
and coordinate maximum,
\begin{align*}
\max_{j = 1, \ \hdots, \ n-1} { \lvrv{ \pri{\gamma}_{B, \ j} (t) } } \leq \cfrac{B}{3n}.
\end{align*}
Outside of this set (that is, where we have these bounds), we have, by computation, that
\begin{align*}
\deriv{t} f(t, \gamma_B(t)) = \pderiv[f]{x_1} (t, \gamma_B(t)) + \sum_{j=2}^{n} \pderiv[f]{x_j} (t, \gamma_B(t)) \cdot \pri{\gamma}_{B, \ j-1} (t),
\end{align*}
which is claimed to be less than $\cfrac{B}{3}$. In the sum, we have that the $\pri{\gamma}_{B, \ j-1}(t)$ are each less than $\cfrac{B}{3n}$, and the derivatives in that same product are each less than $1$ -- making the entire sum at most $\cfrac{B}{3}$ -- but the first summand is greater than $B$ regardless, and so we have a contradiction. That is, as soon as this set of small measure isn't everything, this contradiction occurs. Thus, once $B > C$, we run into trouble.
\end{proof}
Now with that, we truly are done (this section)! Depending on your particular interests, this rather technical proof may have seemed either garish or quite snazzy -- but either way, we are now left with a powerful result, and the first of the major two we will be using to prove the \pwt. If this sort of technicality is not exactly your wheelhouse -- well, then perhaps the model theory arena isn't the path to go down -- but you might be happy to hear that the next section is a fair bit different, and it would not be inconceivable that those not so fond of this material find themselves quite enjoying what's coming up. Depending on the sort of number theory you study/have studied, some of how we go about things may strike you as a bit odd in the approach to number-theoretic proofs, but only time will tell. Much like we went on to refer to the \emph{\om bit} as \textbf{parameterization}, we will similarly start calling this number-theoretic bit the \textbf{diophantine part} -- which we note that we \emph{do not} capitalize, following the convention of the lectures.