-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
section_16.tex
191 lines (141 loc) · 18.3 KB
/
section_16.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% section.tex %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
%
% sample section
%
% Use this file as a template for your own input.
%
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% Springer-Verlag %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
%\motto{Use the template \emph{section.tex} to style the various elements of your section content.}
%\section{Algebraic Dimensionality: A Second, and (Perhaps) More Enlightening Approach}
\subsection{Model-Theoretic Dimension: Once More with Feeling}
\label{chap:alg_dimensionality} % Always give a unique label
% use \sectionmark{}
% to alter or adjust the section heading in the running head
\sectionmark{Some Introductions}
What we just worked through was broadly a very natural extension of the ideas we'd been toying with so far, and the idea of defining dimensionality by cells is a very sensible one indeed. However, the antsy and number theoretically inclined amongst you may be wary of how little of that sort has cropped up so far. Fear not then, our brethren and sistren in the fine and noble study of numbers and the little things they do -- as we now examine the idea of dimensionality from an \emph{algebraic} perspective and begin to work on the ideas that will come to unite the logical world of \omy with that of our own (not to expose our biases too blatantly). We will come to the wonderful conclusion that, in fact, these two notions are one and the same. We can start to drop the veil of pretense we have been vaguely shrouding this whole affair in -- although you would be in the know had you read the introduction in its entirety or even just the Table of Contents. Importantly, this idea will lead us to one of the important tools that allows the \pwt to work at all; that being this connection between algebra, \nt and \omy that together can put together something bigger and more wonderful than each constituent on its own. So, dear reader, please enjoy a rehashing of much of what you saw just a section ago, but now through an entirely different lens -- one that will perhaps expose you to some ideas and inner workings you'd not thought of or seen previously.
\bigskip
\centerline{\rule{0.3333\linewidth}{.2pt}}
\smallskip
\begin{svgraybox}
As in Sections \ref{chap:connectedness} and now \ref{chap:defn_dimensionality}, we will continue in our assumption that we have $\M$ an \om expansion of an \emph{ordered} field, $(M, <, +, \cdot, 0, 1)$, and prove things about this construction in generality.
\end{svgraybox}
Although at no point will we be diving deeply into the depths of model theory and all the fun/horror that this may entail (depending on who you ask), this is going to be the part of the course that relies most heavily on \emph{some} knowledge of model theory. There's little to do to get around that besides having little heuristics in one's head that make things \emph{kind of make sense} enough to not worry about it too much. All this said, the reader who's not even heard the term `model theory' in their life should not be intimidated, as we will be doing our best to hold your hand (or not as you see fit) through the dicier parts of this section, and so much as we hate to keep using this phraseology, belabouring that which may be very obvious to one of a different background. While this may not have been mentioned before, as a series of papers (or more likely document on a computer of some variety), it is easy but vastly rewarding to jump over sections you feel eminently comfortable about with a reckless abandon. This is true for all, but I hope the one professor I hope does get to at least the vast majority of words written here. But for anyone else -- skip judiciously, and skip as if you've much better things to do (which you likely do).
\subsubsection{So How Does One Define Dimension?}
\label{sec:alg_dim}
\noindent Tempting though it is to answer ``depends on who you ask'' and move on with our day, the question does bear significant thought. We start with the following definition (and promise we are not trying to induce d\'ej\`a Vu):
\begin{definition}[Algebraic Dimension]
\
Unlike in the previous section, we will \emph{not} be starting with a definition of the algebraic dimension and working from there -- you simply are not yet prepared, given the content discussed so far. We now back up a little bit and will return to this topic when more sufficiently prepared. Suffice it to say for now that our definition of dimension will be reliant on the idea of \emph{algebraic} (and then, equivalently, \emph{\defnb}) closures (in the model-theoretic sense).
\label{defn:alg_dim_fake}
\end{definition}
\subsubsection{Some Recollections or Introductions}
Here we recall for some, and for others introduce for the first time, some of the rudimentary ideas of model theory, and in particular of how one goes about defining a model-theoretic or algebraic closure of a set -- and then go on similarly to before to use this to define dimensionality.
\subsubsection{On Closures of Various Types}
\begin{definition}[Algebraic Closure]
We say some $A \subseteq M$, then the \textbf{model-theoretic algebraic closure of $A$}, which we will denote by $\acl{A}$, is the union of all finite $A$-\defnb subsets (in $\M$) of $M$.
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}[Definable Closure]
Again, given $A \subseteq M$, then the \textbf{\defnb closure of $A$}, denoted $\dcl{A}$, is given by the union of all $A$-\defnb singletons.
\end{definition}
Note perhaps a more careful attention to parameters being paid here than in previous sections -- precision here concerning the topic is, not to say, of greater importance than elsewhere, but can much more easily lead to confusion if not properly, clearly, and rigorously attended to.
In our setting, in particular in reference to the order-structure our models possess, these seemingly disparate definitions of closure actually coincide -- that is,
\begin{align*}
\acl{A} = \dcl{A}.
\end{align*}
For convenience, we will, in general, simply work with the definable closure.
\pagebreak
\subsubsection{Some Easy Properties}
\begin{proposition}[Basically Free]
\leavevmode
Let $A \subseteq M$. Then
\begin{enumerate}
\item $A \subseteq \dcl{A}$
\item $\dcl{\dcl{A}} = \dcl{A}$
\item $\dcl{A} = \bigcup \left\{ \ \dcl{\{a_1, \hdots, a_n\}} \colon n \in \N, \ a_j \in A \ \right\}$
\end{enumerate}
\end{proposition}
The third of these properties is referred to as having \emph{finite character}. These each feel reasonably obvious enough that we can go without proof, and the interested reader should have little to no trouble coming up with one themselves. The \emph{non}-trivial property, however, that we \emph{will} be proving is referred to as the \emph{Exchange lemma}, which we will curiously notate as a theorem.
\subsubsection{A Less Easy Property}
\begin{theorem}[Exchange (Pillay \& Steinhorn \cite{pillay_definable_1986})]
\label{thm:exchange}
Suppose $A \subseteq M$, and $a, b \in M$. Then if $b \in \dcl{A \cup \{ a \}}$, but $b \not\in \dcl{A}$, then we may `swap' $a$ and $b$, concluding that $a \in \dcl{A \cup \{ b \}}$.
\end{theorem}
Whilst this may seem apropos of nothing and not terribly well-motivated, with a bit of squinting, head-scratching, and perhaps dusting off a copy of \emph{Linear Algebra and Applications 6e} or some other such undergraduate textbook, you may realize that this is, in fact, a generalization of a fact you know quite well -- the Steinitz Exchange Lemma; that is, that any two bases of isomorphic (finite) vector spaces contain the same number of elements. Much like many model-theoretic results, and is, in a sense, sort of the point of model theory, we see this sort of thing often: where something abstract-feeling and seemingly far-removed has immediate consequences should specification to any particular model be made. Now let's prove this, relying heavily on the \Mt to do so.
\begin{proof}[of Exchange (Theorem \ref{thm:exchange})]
Adding constants for elements of $A$, we may suppose that $A = \emptyset$. So, then every $b \in \dcl{\{a\}}$ and \emph{not} in $\dcl{\emptyset}$. Since $b \in \dcl{\{a\}}$, then there is an $\esdefnb$ function, $f$, with $a \in \dom{f} \subseteq M$ and such that $f(a) = b$ (by definition).
Since $\dom{f}$ is $\esdefnb$, it is a finite union of $\esdefnb$ points and $\esdefnb$ intervals. Supposing $a$ was one such point, then $a$ would be $\esdefnb$, and by $b$ in the \defnbcl of $a$, we would also have $b$ $\esdefnb$ -- but we know it not to be by assumption, and so this is a contradiction. Thus, $a$ is \emph{not} a point in $\dom{f}$, and we can thus assume $\dom{f}$ to be an $\esdefnb$ open interval, $I$, with $a \in I$. By \Mt, we can assume that f is strictly monotonic (or constant) on $I$. If constant, then
\begin{align*}
b = f(a) = f(m)
\end{align*}
for $m$ the midpoint of $I$ (which must be $\esdefnb$ by I $\esdefnb$), and further by $f \esdefnb$, so too is $b \esdefnb$. Again, this contradiction implies $f$ is non-constant, and so must be strictly monotonic.
Then, $\inv{f}(b) = a$ is well defined, and so $a$ is \defnb from $b$ -- that is, $a \in \dcl{\{b\}}$ as desired.
\smartqed
\end{proof}
Having those easy properties above (in particular finite character and idempotence of $\dclop$) along with exchange means that the concept of \defnbcl is what is referred to as a \emph{\pregeom}. That is, $\dclop$ is a \pregeom in any model of the theory of $\M$. For those of us who have not previously encountered the idea of \pregeoms, this is significant because a \pregeom comes equipped with a notion of \emph{dimension} -- which is exactly what we're after right now. Even if you are unfamiliar with the term, we can assure you, dear reader, with almost complete certainty that you are intimately familiar with several examples of these objects. Vector spaces, projective and affine spaces, and algebraically closed fields are all examples of \pregeoms -- although it should be noted that these are of quite different classifications (within the realm of this area of study) from one another \cite{pillay_geometric_1996}.
Suppose $A \subseteq M$, $\aMn[a]{n}$. We define
\begin{align*}
\dim{\sfrac{a}{A}} = \min{ \left\{ \ \card{\pri{a}} \ \colon \ \pri{a} \textrm{ a subtuple of } a \textrm{ and } a \in \dcl{A \cup \pri{a}}^n \ \right\} }.
\end{align*}
An alternative characterization is as follows: we call some $X \subseteq M$ \emph{independent} over $A$ if for every $x \in X$, we have $x \not\in \dcl{A \cup (X \setminus \{ x \})}$. Then, the dimension as first defined is given by the \emph{maximum} cardinality of a subtuple which is independent over $A$. That is,
\begin{align*}
%\sfrac{a}{A} = \max{ \left\{ \card{X} \ \colon \ X \subseteq M \textrm{ is independent over } A \right\} }
\dim{ \sfrac{a}{A} } = \max{ \left\{ \card{X} \ \colon \ \forall x \in X \ . \ x \not\in \dcl{A \cup (X \setminus \{ x \})} \right\} }
\end{align*}
We assume that $\M$ is sufficiently saturated and that all parameter sets are small relative to this saturation claim. We will not be discussing at any great (or really even short) length what this means, but we will note that this is actually a stronger condition than we necessarily need to take -- it is just a convenience that will make things a bit easier down the line. Consider now the following definition:
\begin{definition}
Suppose $\XMn[X]{n}$ is \defnb over $A$. Then we define the dimension of $X$ to be, predictably,
\begin{align*}
\dim{X} = \max{ \left\{ \ \dim{\sfrac{a}{A}} \ \colon \ a \in X \ \right\} }.
\end{align*}
\label{defn:alg_dim}
\end{definition}
\begin{remark}
Without the assurance of sufficient saturation, the points $\left\{ \sfrac{a}{A} \right\}$ may not even exist, and so instead, we could quantify over all elementary extensions of our model -- but for our purposes, we acknowledge and go on to ignore this small potential snag.
\end{remark}
Although we have been referring to some set of parameters, $A$, throughout, it turns out that as long as you take a ``small'' set (again, relative to the saturation), then the choice of $A$ does not truly affect the dimension of the definable $X$. To be clear, we will not be clear about quantifying appropriate ``smallness'' relative to the saturation in this course and simply sweep the issue under the rug for perhaps a secondary, more rigorous course on the topic.
Informally, we can envision that for two sufficiently small sets of parameters, $A \subseteq B \subseteq M$, we can clearly see that for \defnb $\XMn{n}$, we get $\dim{X}_B \leq \dim{X}_A$. Supposing the dimension with respect to $A$ to be $k$ with point $a \in X$ witnessing the dimension, without loss of generality we can take the first $(\vonevm{a}{k})$ to be independent over $A$ -- but then by saturation, we can similarly find $k$ independent such $(\vonevm{b}{k})$ over $B$ with type matching that for our $a$. Then, our $(\vonevm{b}{k})$ extends to $b \in X$, and so $\dim{X}_B \geq k$ as well. Thus, the choice of parameters is irrelevant (again, given this caveat).
\subsection{Reconciling Dimensionality}
Ultimately, our goal here is to show that the dimension we are currently discussing is, in fact, equivalent to that discussed in the previous (previous) section. To this end, consider the following lemma, which topologically characterizes the independence of points.
\begin{lemma}
Suppose that $\aMn[a]{n}$, and $\AM[A]$ (small). Then, the coordinates, $(\vonevm{a}{n})$ of $a$ are independent over $A$ if and only if every $\Adefnb$ set $\XMn[X]{n}$ with $a \in X$ has \inhb interior.
\label{lemma:indep_top}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}[of Lemma \ref{lemma:indep_top}]
We start with the easy direction, and use a proof by contradiction. Suppose $\vonevm{a}{n}$ are \emph{dependent} over $A$. Without loss of generality, take $a_n \in \dcl{A \cup \{ \vonevm{a}{n-1} \}}$. Then, our language contains some formula, $\phi$, with parameters from $A$, such that $a_n$ is the unique $x$ satisfying $\phi(\vonevm{a}{n-1}, x)$ in $\M$. Now, let
\begin{align*}
X = \left\{ \ \aMn[x]{n} \ \colon \ \phi(\vonevm{x}{n}) \textrm{ holds and } x_n \textrm{ uniquely satisfies } \phi(\vonevm{x}{n}) \ \right\}.
\end{align*}
By uniqueness of $x_n$, we must have that $X$ has an empty interior and $a \in X$. Now, for the other direction, we use \cd by induction on $n$.
If $n = 1$, and if $a_1$ is independent over $A$, then $a_1$ is not in any finite $\Adefnb$ set. So, if $a_1 \in X$ for $X$ $\Adefnb$, then $X$ is infinite, and so contains an open interval. Thus, it has \inhb interior.
\pagebreak
Supposing this holds for $M^n$, we take $\aMn[a]{n+1}$ with coordinates $(\vonevm{a}{n+1})$ independent over $A$, and suppose $\XMn[X]{n+1}$ to be $\Adefnb$ and having $a \in X$.
\begin{svgraybox}
It bears mentioning here, as we are about to use this fact but have neither mentioned, proved, nor intend to prove it, but the following is true: If we have a set of cells decomposed over some set of parameters, $A$, then we can take each of those cells to be defined over that same set of parameters.
\end{svgraybox}
Recall that by \cd, we get to suppose that $X = C$ is a cell defined over $A$. As such, $C$ may either be
\begin{itemize}
\item $C = \graph{f}$ for $\funcdom{f}{\pri{C}}{M}$ $\Adefnb$ -- in which case $a_{n+1} = f(\vonevm{a}{n})$, leading to a contradiction of independence over $A$; \ or
\item $C = (f, g)_{\pri{C}}$ for $\funcdom{f,g}{\pri{C}}{M}$ \cont and $\Adefnb$ with $f < g$ (or one of the functions $\pm \infty$). This latter case must be true by exhaustion.
\end{itemize}
So, we get that $(\vonevm{a}{n}) \in \pri{C}$. We have that $\vonevm{a}{n}$ are independent over $A$ and that $\pri{C}$ is an $\Adefnb$ set containing them -- and so must have interior. By the inductive hypothesis, $\pri{C}$ is an open-cell, and then so too must be $C$, meaning $X$ has \inhb interior.
With both directions proved, we are now finished.
\smartqed
\end{proof}
Immediately putting that lemma to work, we can show the following:
\begin{proposition}
Let $\XMn[X]{n}$ an $\Adefnb$ set, and $k \leq n$ a possible dimension for $A$. Then $\dim{X} \geq k$ if and only if there is a coordinate-projection, $\funcdom{\pi}{M^n}{M^k}$ such that the projection $\pi(X)$ has \inhb interior.
\label{prop:inhb_coord_proj}
\end{proposition}
\begin{remark}
The maximum such possible $k$ is sometimes referred to as the \emph{topological dimension} of the set -- although (and as we have bemoaned before) this term is also used to refer to a variety of inequivalent concepts. It is also perhaps worth noting that, in our setting, this topological dimension agrees with the definable (or cellular) dimension; just as we are about to show, so too does the algebraic dimension we have been discussing here.
\end{remark}
\begin{corollary}[Agreement of Dimension Definitions]
For $\XMn[X]{n}$ a \defnb set, the notion of $\dim{X}$ as described in this section (Definition \ref{defn:alg_dim}) agrees with that of the previous section (Definition \ref{defn:defn_dim}).
\label{cor:dim_agree}
\end{corollary}
This is stated without proof, which shouldn't be even near out of the reach of the reader who has been feeling confident with the content thus far. It would not be unwise to take a go at it as a test of one's familiarity and skill with the ideas and the sorts of proofs we have seen thus far.
Now, we turn our attention back to proving the previously neglected proposition.
\begin{proof}[of Proposition \ref{prop:inhb_coord_proj}]
We start with the forward direction. Suppose $\dim{X} \geq k$. Then for our $a \in X$ of interest, there is an $n$-tuple that, without loss of generality, can be taken to be $(\vonevm{a}{n})$ with first $k$ coordinates non-trivial -- ie. that has coordinates independent over $A$. Then, should we take the projection onto the first $k$ coordinates, we know that $(\vonevm{a}{k})$ lies in that projection, and so by the lemma we just proved, that projection has \inhb interior.
Now for the other direction, we suppose such a projection, $\funcdom{\pi}{M^n}{M^k}$ exists such that $\pi(X)$ has \inhb interior. Again, we suppose for convenience that this occurs for the first $k$ coordinates. Then, $\pi(X)$ is definitionally $\Adefnb$, and having non-empty interior, must contain an open $\Adefnb$ box, $U = I_1 \times \hdots \times I_k$. Using saturation, we inductively find $(\vonevm{a}{k}) \in U$ independent over $A$. Then, taking $a \in X$ such that $\pi(a) = (\vonevm{a}{k})$, we have that this witnesses the dimension of $X$ is no less than $k$. So, $\dim{X} \geq k$.
\end{proof}